Skip to main content
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian
  • Log in
  • Log out
  • My Cart

Main menu

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Latest Articles
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • Archive
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • Highlights from Latest Articles
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Purpose and Scope
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • For Reviewers
    • Author FAQ
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian

User menu

  • Log in
  • Log out
  • My Cart

Search

  • Advanced search
Home
Home

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Latest Articles
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • Archive
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • Highlights from Latest Articles
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Purpose and Scope
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • For Reviewers
    • Author FAQ

New Research In

Physical Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Physics
  • Chemistry
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Applied Mathematics
  • Applied Physical Sciences
  • Astronomy
  • Computer Sciences
  • Earth, Atmospheric, and Planetary Sciences
  • Engineering
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Mathematics
  • Statistics

Social Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Economic Sciences
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Political Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Social Sciences

Biological Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Agricultural Sciences
  • Anthropology
  • Applied Biological Sciences
  • Biochemistry
  • Biophysics and Computational Biology
  • Cell Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Evolution
  • Genetics
  • Immunology and Inflammation
  • Medical Sciences
  • Microbiology
  • Neuroscience
  • Pharmacology
  • Physiology
  • Plant Biology
  • Population Biology
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Sustainability Science
  • Systems Biology

Economics and the evolution of life histories

Alan R. Rogers
PNAS August 5, 2003 100 (16) 9114-9115; https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1733942100
Alan R. Rogers
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Birth and death are subjects of perennial interest. They are shaped by both physiology and behavior, which are themselves shaped (presumably) by natural selection. Thus, it seems natural to suppose that evolutionary ideas would form the core of demography. This, however, is not the case. Students of birth and death are largely divided: social scientists call the subject demography, and evolutionists call it life history evolution. In this issue of PNAS, Ronald Lee (1) proposes a theory that may help heal this divide.

Lee's theory is about aging. Within evolutionary biology, discussion of this subject has been dominated for decades by two theories: mutation accumulation and antagonistic pleiotropy (2). The first of these holds that selection is less effective at removing harmful mutations that act in old age, so such mutations accumulate. The second holds that some mutations are beneficial in youth but harmful later on. Such mutations accumulate because selection is more responsive to early effects than to late ones. Kirkwood's (3) “disposable soma” theory describes a mechanism that can plausibly generate antagonistic pleiotropy.

Lee's focus is on parental care and other transfers of resources between individuals of different ages. When a woman dies at, say, age 30, the death deprives her children of the care they would have received from her. Thus, a mutation that increases the mortality of 30-year-olds has harmful effects at several ages. This has the flavor of antagonistic pleiotropy, but the theory is broader in that it encompasses cases in which the early and late effects are both harmful or both helpful. The real value of the new theory, however, is in its success in wedding an economic model of exchange between individuals to the evolutionary theory of aging.

Lee's article addresses several important questions. The first of these has to do with the age profile of mortality during childhood. Among humans and many other species, death rates decline dramatically during the initial part of life (4, 5). This pattern is pronounced in some species but apparently absent in others (6). Why should this be? The first attempt at an answer was made 70 years ago by Fisher (7), who observed that an average 15-year-old will contribute more to future generations than will a newborn because the 15-year-old is less likely to die before reproducing. Thus, he argued, selection affects genes more strongly if they are expressed in 15-year-olds than if they are expressed in newborns. From this perspective, high newborn mortality results from the relatively weak selection acting on them.

This argument seemed to fit the facts and held sway for 36 years, until Hamilton (8) found its flaw in 1966. Fisher had been right to ask what contribution each age class makes to future generations. But what matters is the contribution of the age class as a whole, not the contribution per individual. Correcting this mistake, Hamilton found that the force of selection on genes affecting mortality is constant during childhood. It is as strong for newborns as it is for 15-year-olds. Thus, the revised theory fails completely to account for the facts of juvenile mortality.

If selection favors production of children, how could it favor an early end to fertility?

There have been other suggestions (9, 10). Perhaps the most influential idea is what Hamilton (8) called the principle of sibling replacement. In species with intense parental care, offspring are costly. When one dies, the parental resources that are freed can be used to produce another. If this must happen, it is best for it to happen early, for this minimizes the parental resources squandered on reproductive failures. Thus, selection should shove vulnerabilities into early childhood. This idea was anticipated by Fisher (7) and has been discussed by many later authors. Until now, however, there has been no theoretical model capable of predicting the magnitude of the effect. Lee's article fills this hole and sheds light on a second issue: the early menopause of human females.

This is a puzzle that takes us to the opposite end of the female lifespan. If selection favors production of children, how could it ever favor an early end to fertility? Why do women not continue producing babies into old age? Or, to look at the problem from the other direction, how does selection weed out harmful mutations that increase mortality late in life? The force of selection affecting genes expressed in 50-year-old women should depend on the contribution that such women make to future generations. But if these women have stopped reproducing, this contribution would seem to be nil. Thus, harmful mutations acting late in life should accumulate and death should follow soon after reproduction stops (11).

In most species, this is exactly what does happen. But there are exceptions. Among humans and some whales, females may live long after reproduction has ceased (12–14). Williams (11) suggested that older females have more to gain by helping their existing children and grandchildren than by producing more of their own. Thus, selection opposes mutations that would increase either the mortality or the fertility of older females.

Although other explanations have been proposed (15–18), there is an abiding interest in variants of Williams's hypothesis. In 1993 I was able to reject the view that early menopause evolved to protect women from childbirth mortality. I was unable to reject the “opportunity cost” hypothesis, which holds that each new child reduces the woman's ability to enhance the survival and fertility of existing children and grandchildren (19). Since then, Shanley and Kirkwood (20) have found a reasonable fit to a model combining both of these hypotheses, and ethnographic research has generated clear evidence that older women have a beneficial effect on children and grandchildren in traditional societies (21, 22). Comparisons across primate taxa show that, after regressing out the lengths of childhood and lifespan, birth rates are higher in humans than in other apes (23, 24). This is all consistent with the “grandmother hypothesis,” which holds that the labor of older women accelerates the rate of childbearing in humans. Yet there is still room for skepticism. We might expect human fertility to exceed that of apes simply because the human population has been growing and ape populations have been declining in recent decades. Other efforts to test variants of Williams's idea have failed to yield significant results (25). Thus, this issue is still open after a decade of accelerating research interest.

Lee (1) brings a new style of mathematical model to these issues. He begins with the standard renewal equation of life history theory (10). Onto this he grafts a “balance equation,” which stipulates that mean lifetime consumption must equal mean lifetime production. This latter condition carries a lot of freight: it allows an analysis of evolutionary equilibria in the context of parental care and other transfers of resources between individuals.

This model is very general. It assumes that fertility increases with consumption, that mortality declines with consumption, and so on, but does not make specific assumptions about the forms of any of these functions. It does, however, make one restrictive assumption: it assumes that production equals consumption within each genotypic class. This means that there are no transfers of resources between individuals of different genotypes. But in an outbred sexual population, a rare mutant is equally likely to have a normal or a mutant mother. If transfers are from mother to daughter, half of the transfers received by a rare mutant will be across genotypic classes. Thus, Lee's model implicitly assumes clonal reproduction in which each individual has a single parent of identical genotype.

There is a long tradition in ecology of building clonal models to study sexual organisms (26). Such models are useful because they simplify problems that are otherwise complex, yet often reveal essential features. They should, of course, be regarded cautiously, because one sometimes has to eat one's words when the sexual model fails to replicate the clonal one (27).

The model has one other limitation. It depends critically on the shape of what Lee calls the “balance curve.” This is the relationship, as implied by the balance equation, between growth rate and γ, an index of consumption. The analysis depends on this curve having the shape of an inverted “U,” but there is no clear delineation of the circumstances under which this is true. This is no fatal flaw, for it is easy to show that the inverted “U” is there in at least some cases, but it will be important to work out the conditions under which this assumption holds.

Lee shows that the force of selection on mutations affecting mortality has two components, one measuring expected future births (the Hamilton effect) and the other measuring expected future net production (the transfer effect). At evolutionary equilibrium, the Hamilton effect falls to zero so that selection is affected by the transfer effect alone.

The transfer effect increases throughout childhood because children consume more than they produce. Thus, mutations that increase mortality are removed more rapidly if they act late in childhood than if they act early. This may account for the decline in mortality during childhood. It formalizes the sibling replacement hypothesis of Hamilton (8). Net productivity is also positive in postmenopausal women, so the transfer effect remains positive after reproduction has ceased. This formalizes the hypothesis of Williams (11). Thus, both hypotheses receive support in the context of a single model.

Although the analysis is entirely qualitative, the equilibrium result is in terms of a quantity, the transfer effect, that can be estimated. Thus, Lee is able to show an excellent agreement between the entire age profile of human mortality rates and the predicted force of selection. This is the most comprehensive evolutionary theory of aging that we have seen to date.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for comments from Elizabeth Cashdan, Kristen Hawkes, Henry Harpending, Jon Seger, James Wood, and Ronald Lee.

Footnotes

    • ↵* E-mail: rogers{at}anthro.utah.edu.

    • See companion article on page 9637.

    • Copyright © 2003, The National Academy of Sciences

    References

    1. ↵
      Lee, R. D. (2003) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 100, 9637–9642.pmid:12878733
      OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    2. ↵
      Rose, M. R. (1991) Evolutionary Biology of Aging (Oxford Univ. Press, New York).
    3. ↵
      Kirkwood, T. B. & Rose, M. R. (1991) Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London B 332, 15–24.pmid:1677205
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    4. ↵
      Hill, K. & Hurtado, A. M. (1996) Ache Life History: The Ecology and Demography of a Foraging People (Aldine de Gruyter, Hawthorne, NY).
    5. ↵
      Mace, R. (2000) Anim. Behav. 59, 1–10.pmid:10640361
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    6. ↵
      Martinez, D. E. (1998) Exp. Gerontol. 33, 217–225.pmid:9615920
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    7. ↵
      Fisher, R. A. (1958) The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection (Dover, New York), 2nd Ed.
    8. ↵
      Hamilton, W. D. (1966) J. Theor. Biol. 12, 12–45.pmid:6015424
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    9. ↵
      McNeill, W. H. (1976) Plagues and Peoples (Anchor/Doubleday, Garden City, NY).
    10. ↵
      Charlesworth, B. (1994) Evolution in Age-Structured Populations (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, U.K.), 2nd Ed.
    11. ↵
      Williams, G. C. (1957) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 11, 398–411.
      OpenUrlCrossRef
    12. ↵
      Kasuya, T. & Marsh, H. (1984) in Reproduction in Whales, Dolphins, and Porpoises: Proceedings of the Conference, Cetacean Reproduction, Estimating Parameters for Stock Assessment and Management, La Jolla, California, November 28–December 7, 1981, eds. Perrin, W. F., Brownell, R. L. & DeMaster, D. P. (International Whaling Commission, Cambridge, U.K.), Vol. 6, pp. 260–309.
      OpenUrl
    13. Hrdy, S. B. (1981) in Other Ways of Growing Old, eds. Amoss, P. & Harrell, S. (Stanford Univ. Press, Stanford, CA), pp. 59–76.
    14. ↵
      Finch, C. E. (1990) Longevity, Senescence, and the Genome (Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago).
    15. ↵
      Weiss, K. M. (1981) in Other Ways of Growing Old, eds. Amoss, P. & Harrell, S. (Stanford Univ. Press, Stanford, CA), pp. 25–52.
    16. Wood, J. W., O'Connor, K. A., Holman, D. J., Brindle, E., Barsom, S. H. & Grimes, M. A. (2003) in Homo-unsere Herkunft und Zukunft, ed. Schultz, M. (Cuvillier, Gottingen, Germany), pp. 483–490.
    17. Turke, P. W. (1997) Evol. Hum. Behav. 18, 3–13.
      OpenUrlCrossRef
    18. ↵
      Austad, S. N. (1997) in Between Zeus and the Salmon: The Biodemography of Longevity, eds. Wachter, K. W. & Finch, C. E. (Natl. Acad. Press, Washington, DC), pp. 161–174.
    19. ↵
      Rogers, A. R. (1993) Evol. Ecol. 7, 406–420.
      OpenUrlCrossRef
    20. ↵
      Shanley, D. P. & Kirkwood, T. B. L. (2001) BioEssays 23, 282–287.pmid:11223885
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    21. ↵
      Hawkes, K., O'Connell, J. F. & Blurton Jones, N. G. (1997) Curr. Anthropol. 38, 551–578.
      OpenUrlCrossRef
    22. ↵
      Sear, R., Mace, R. & McGregor, I. A. (2000) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 267, 1641–1647.
      OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    23. ↵
      Alverez, H. P. (2000) Am. J. Phys. Anthropol. 113, 435–450.pmid:11042542
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    24. ↵
      Hawkes, K., O'Connell, J. F., Blurton Jones, N. G., Alvarez, H. & Charnov, E. L. (1998) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 95, 1336–1339.pmid:9448332
      OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    25. ↵
      Hill, K. & Hurtado, M. (1991) Hum. Nat. 2, 313–350.
      OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    26. ↵
      Rogers, A. R. (1990) Ethol. Sociobiol. 11, 479–495.
      OpenUrlCrossRef
    27. ↵
      Rogers, A. R. (1994) in Human Reproductive Decisions: Biological and Biosocial Perspectives, ed. Dunbar, R. (Macmillan, Basingstoke, U.K.), pp. 76–95.
    View Abstract
    PreviousNext
    Back to top
    Article Alerts
    Email Article

    Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on PNAS.

    NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

    Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
    Economics and the evolution of life histories
    (Your Name) has sent you a message from PNAS
    (Your Name) thought you would like to see the PNAS web site.
    Citation Tools
    Economics and the evolution of life histories
    Alan R. Rogers
    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Aug 2003, 100 (16) 9114-9115; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1733942100

    Citation Manager Formats

    • BibTeX
    • Bookends
    • EasyBib
    • EndNote (tagged)
    • EndNote 8 (xml)
    • Medlars
    • Mendeley
    • Papers
    • RefWorks Tagged
    • Ref Manager
    • RIS
    • Zotero
    Request Permissions
    Share
    Economics and the evolution of life histories
    Alan R. Rogers
    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Aug 2003, 100 (16) 9114-9115; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1733942100
    del.icio.us logo Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo CiteULike logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
    • Tweet Widget
    • Facebook Like
    • Mendeley logo Mendeley
    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences: 116 (7)
    Current Issue

    Submit

    Sign up for Article Alerts

    Jump to section

    • Article
      • Acknowledgments
      • Footnotes
      • References
    • Info & Metrics
    • PDF

    You May Also be Interested in

    Several aspects of the proposal, which aims to expand open access, require serious discussion and, in some cases, a rethink.
    Opinion: “Plan S” falls short for society publishers—and for the researchers they serve
    Several aspects of the proposal, which aims to expand open access, require serious discussion and, in some cases, a rethink.
    Image credit: Dave Cutler (artist).
    Several large or long-lived animals seem strangely resistant to developing cancer. Elucidating the reasons why could lead to promising cancer-fighting strategies in humans.
    Core Concept: Solving Peto’s Paradox to better understand cancer
    Several large or long-lived animals seem strangely resistant to developing cancer. Elucidating the reasons why could lead to promising cancer-fighting strategies in humans.
    Image credit: Shutterstock.com/ronnybas frimages.
    Featured Profile
    PNAS Profile of NAS member and biochemist Hao Wu
     Nonmonogamous strawberry poison frog (Oophaga pumilio).  Image courtesy of Yusan Yang (University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh).
    Putative signature of monogamy
    A study suggests a putative gene-expression hallmark common to monogamous male vertebrates of some species, namely cichlid fishes, dendrobatid frogs, passeroid songbirds, common voles, and deer mice, and identifies 24 candidate genes potentially associated with monogamy.
    Image courtesy of Yusan Yang (University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh).
    Active lifestyles. Image courtesy of Pixabay/MabelAmber.
    Meaningful life tied to healthy aging
    Physical and social well-being in old age are linked to self-assessments of life worth, and a spectrum of behavioral, economic, health, and social variables may influence whether aging individuals believe they are leading meaningful lives.
    Image courtesy of Pixabay/MabelAmber.

    More Articles of This Classification

    • Solution to the 50-year-old Okazaki-fragment problem
    • Musical pleasure and musical emotions
    • Biodiversity conservation of Morlocks in west-central Texas
    Show more

    Related Content

    • Rethinking the evolutionary theory of aging: Transfers, not births, shape senescence in social species
    • Scopus
    • PubMed
    • Google Scholar

    Cited by...

    • Reproductive protein protects functionally sterile honey bee workers from oxidative stress
    • Older age becomes common late in human evolution
    • Scopus (8)
    • Google Scholar

    Similar Articles

    Site Logo
    Powered by HighWire
    • Submit Manuscript
    • Twitter
    • Facebook
    • RSS Feeds
    • Email Alerts

    Articles

    • Current Issue
    • Latest Articles
    • Archive

    PNAS Portals

    • Classics
    • Front Matter
    • Teaching Resources
    • Anthropology
    • Chemistry
    • Physics
    • Sustainability Science

    Information

    • Authors
    • Editorial Board
    • Reviewers
    • Press
    • Site Map

    Feedback    Privacy/Legal

    Copyright © 2019 National Academy of Sciences. Online ISSN 1091-6490