Skip to main content
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian
  • Log in
  • My Cart

Main menu

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Latest Articles
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • Archive
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • Highlights from Latest Articles
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Purpose and Scope
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • For Reviewers
    • Author FAQ
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian

User menu

  • Log in
  • My Cart

Search

  • Advanced search
Home
Home

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Latest Articles
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • Archive
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • Highlights from Latest Articles
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Purpose and Scope
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • For Reviewers
    • Author FAQ

New Research In

Physical Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Physics
  • Chemistry
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Applied Mathematics
  • Applied Physical Sciences
  • Astronomy
  • Computer Sciences
  • Earth, Atmospheric, and Planetary Sciences
  • Engineering
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Mathematics
  • Statistics

Social Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Economic Sciences
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Political Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Social Sciences

Biological Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Agricultural Sciences
  • Anthropology
  • Applied Biological Sciences
  • Biochemistry
  • Biophysics and Computational Biology
  • Cell Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Evolution
  • Genetics
  • Immunology and Inflammation
  • Medical Sciences
  • Microbiology
  • Neuroscience
  • Pharmacology
  • Physiology
  • Plant Biology
  • Population Biology
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Sustainability Science
  • Systems Biology

Evolvability is a selectable trait

David J. Earl and Michael W. Deem
PNAS August 10, 2004 101 (32) 11531-11536; https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0404656101
David J. Earl
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Michael W. Deem
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  1. Communicated by David Chandler, University of California, Berkeley, CA, June 30, 2004 (received for review April 19, 2004)

  • Article
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

Concomitant with the evolution of biological diversity must have been the evolution of mechanisms that facilitate evolution, because of the essentially infinite complexity of protein sequence space. We describe how evolvability can be an object of Darwinian selection, emphasizing the collective nature of the process. We quantify our theory with computer simulations of protein evolution. These simulations demonstrate that rapid or dramatic environmental change leads to selection for greater evolvability. The selective pressure for large-scale genetic moves such as DNA exchange becomes increasingly strong as the environmental conditions become more uncertain. Our results demonstrate that evolvability is a selectable trait and allow for the explanation of a large body of experimental results.

Darwin was obsessed with variation. His books, considered as an ensemble, devote much more attention to variation than to natural selection, because he knew that no satisfactory theory of evolutionary change could be constructed until the causes of variation and the empirical rule of its form and amount had been elucidated (1).

Whether the propensity to evolve, or evolvability (2–4), can be an object of Darwinian natural selection is a topic of interest. Causality would suggest not because of the apparently anticipatory nature of evolvability (5, 6). Many within the field of evolutionary biology are uncomfortable with the concept that evolvability is a selectable trait. A growing body of experimental data, however, would be explained if evolvability were a selectable trait (7–15).

Higher organisms cannot evolve, or adapt, by germ-line mutation to an environmental change within their own lifetime. Does this mean that lineages and individuals cannot be under selection for evolvability? Although viability is the selection criterion, the genotype that determines the viability arises in a mutated, evolved way from that of the previous generation as a result of base substitution, recombination, transposition, and horizontal gene transfer. These mutational processes are the driving forces of evolution, and their rates fundamentally determine evolvability. The perspective we offer here is that the evolvability of an organism is defined by the rates of genetic change, that genetic change is not always deleterious, and that these rates of genetic change are not fixed and are under selective pressure. That is, the mechanisms that define the rates of change are encoded in the genotype, and so they are selectable. An analogy with thermodynamics illuminates the issue: How is free energy minimized in a physical system of particles despite the difficulty in defining the entropy of a given configuration of the particles? An ensemble of particle configurations allows the definition of free energy and the approach to thermodynamic equilibrium just as a population of evolving organisms allows the definition of and selection for evolvability.

Within the framework of point mutation, base substitution, and recombination, correlations of adaptation with function have been observed. It is known that immunoglobins have evolved such that the mutation rates in complementary determining regions, in which mutation is most likely to generate useful variants, are much higher than those in framework regions (14, 16). Recent data point to a role for DNA polymerases in regulating the somatic hypermutation rate of immunoglobin genes (13, 17). Similarly, codon usage within the influenza hemagglutinin protein seems to be biased to favor more rapid antigenic drift (14). Furthermore, in HIV-1 protease, the probability of mutation is not randomly distributed within the structure but rather concentrated at sites that alter the geometry of the protein-binding domain, conferring significant propensity for antigenic drift (18). Such behavior is not mere curiosity and has widespread implications for drug design and the evolution of drug resistance (19). Stressful conditions may generally provoke activation of error-prone polymerases, triggering a large increase in adaptive rates (20). Not only point mutation but also recombination are widely appreciated to confer increased evolvability (9, 21, 22). Recombination among the hemagglutinin and neuraminidase proteins, for example, is believed to be a significant mechanism leading to the emergence of new virulent strains of influenza (23). Computational and theoretical studies have also shown the persistence under selection of evolvability-enhancing moves in the context of point mutation and recombination evolutionary dynamics (24–29).

The selective forces that lead to the evolution and maintenance of mechanisms for rearrangement, deletion, transfer, and transposition of genetic material, inasmuch as they lead to even greater evolution than point mutation and recombination alone, are of great interest. For example, the development of antibiotic resistance in bacteria has evolved mainly through the swapping of DNA pieces between the evolving bacteria (8, 30). Similarly, the evolution of Escherichia coli from Salmonella is thought to have occurred exclusively from DNA swapping (31). It has been proposed that the success of bacteria as a group stems from a capacity to acquire genes from a large and diverse range of species (32). It would seem, then, that large genetic moves are pervasive and crucial to evolutionary dynamics (6, 8, 10–12, 15, 30, 31, 33–39). Concomitantly, evolvability is enhanced by these larger moves, as shown experimentally for the case of DNA shuffling (32, 40–44). A key question is whether selection for evolvability fosters the husbandry of these moves.

We address here, from a theoretical point of view, selection of evolvability in the presence of large-scale genetic moves. Although the use of the term evolvability has only recently come into vogue in the scientific community, investigations into the evolution of adaptation go back several decades (45–47). Prominent from a theoretical perspective are works in population genetics (48, 49) and game theory (50–52). Despite the insights that these studies give as to the origin and maintenance of evolvability, evolution of and selection for evolvability remains a contested issue primarily because of the causality principle (5, 6). We show here that evolvability is selected for, notwithstanding the constraints imposed by causality, when a system is subject to a constant, random environmental change. This selection for evolvability occurs even when viability as a function of genotype is an extremely complex function, with exponentially many optima, and when the evolving system is unable to reach the global optimum of viability in any one instance of the environment. We demonstrate our results by using computer simulations of protein molecular evolution that incorporate selection in a varying environment. The genotype of a protein molecule is mapped to a complex phenotype by using a generalized NK model in which all assumptions and relevant parameters are known. The selective pressure for evolvability is shown to be greater for larger rates of environmental change. Interestingly, a generalized susceptibility of the system correlates with the fluctuations in the environment, albeit not as a result of generalized linear response theory (53). The addition of selection for evolvability as a phenomenological law to the toolbox of evolutionary theory allows for the explanation of a large body of experimental results.

The Generalized Block NK Model

Whether evolvability is selectable has been a difficult question to answer, primarily because observations in evolutionary biology tend to be correlative in nature and difficult on which to make mechanistic conclusions. Therefore, we consider here the dynamics of evolvability in a well defined theoretical model of protein evolution (54). Within this model of protein structure and function, we have a fixed population of proteins, which we take to be 1,000. We have a microscopic selection criterion, which we take to be the folding and binding of a protein to a substrate. And we have a means of inducing constant, random environmental change.

We model the molecular evolution of protein systems by using a generalization of the NK (55–57) and block NK (58) models that has been used previously to study protein molecular evolution strategies (54) and the immune-system response to vaccination and disease (59). The model includes a population of sequences, upon which selection acts and in which occur genetic mutations. The mutational hierarchy includes both point mutations and large-scale swapping moves, akin to transposition or translocation events. Although the model does not include recombination, such inclusion is not expected to change the results because swapping can be viewed as a powerful form of recombination (54). For example, linkage effects are mitigated even more rapidly by swapping in our model than they would be by recombination. The selection for greater swapping rates in more rapidly changing environments observed in our model parallels results found in studies of the evolution of sex, for which adaptation and variation in a heterogeneous environment is well researched (60).

In the generalized block NK model, each individual evolving protein sequence has an energy that is determined by secondary structural subdomain energies, U sd, subdomain–subdomain interaction energies, U sd–sd, and chemical binding energies, U c. This energy is used as the selection criteria in our studies and is given by Math Within our generalized block NK model, each protein molecule is composed of M = 10 secondary structural subdomains of N = 10 aa in length. We consider five chemically distinct amino acid classes (negative, positive, polar, hydrophobic, and other) and L = 5 different types of subdomains (helices, strands, loops, turns, and others). We therefore have L different subdomain energy functions of the NK form Math where a j is the amino acid type of the jth amino acid in the subdomain, and αi is the type of the ith subdomain. As in previous studies, we consider the case in which the range of the interactions within a subdomain is specified by K = 4 (54, 59). Here σαi is a quenched Gaussian random number with zero mean and a variance of unity, and it is different for each value of its argument for each of the L subdomain types, αi. The interaction energy between secondary subdomain structures is given by Math where we consider D = 6 interactions between secondary structures (54, 59). The zero-mean, unit-variance Gaussian Math and the interacting amino acids, j 1,..., j K, are selected at random for each interaction (i, j, k). In our model, P = 5 aa contribute directly to a binding event, as in a typical pharmacophore, where the chemical binding energy of each amino acid is given by Math where the zero-mean, unit-variance Gaussian σi and the contributing amino acid, i, are chosen at random.

System Evolution and Environmental Change

Our model system maintains a constant population of 1,000 proteins, each protein of 100 aa in length and initially distinct in sequence. The system evolves through the base substitution of single amino acids and through DNA swapping of amino acid subdomains from structural pools representing the five different subdomain types, each containing 250 low-energy subdomain sequences. These moves represent the small-scale adaptation and the large-scale, dramatic evolution that occur in nature. For protein i, n mut(i) point mutations occur per sequence per round of selection. In addition, for protein i, subdomain sequences are replaced randomly with sequences from the same-type low-energy pools with probability p swap(i).

After pool swapping and point mutations, selection occurs, and the 20% lowest-energy protein sequences are kept and amplified to form the population of 1,000 proteins for the next round of selection. The parameters p swap(i) and n mut(i) are allowed to take a log-Gaussian random walk for each protein sequence. This process is repeated for N gen rounds of selection, after which an environmental change is imposed on the system with a severity that is characterized by the parameter p (59). The parameter p is the probability of (i) changing the type of each of the 10 subdomains in the protein sequences, αi in Eq. 2, (ii) changing the amino acids and energies that are involved in subdomain–subdomain interactions, j k and σ(k) ij in Eq. 3, and (iii) changing the amino acids and energies that are involved in the chemical binding, i and σi in Eq. 4. We repeat the process for a total of 100 environmental changes and average our results over 1,000 instances of the ensemble. For each system studied, a steady state in n mut, p swap, and the average energies at the beginning, 〈U〉start, and end, 〈U〉end, of the dynamics in a single instance of the environment is reached after <80 environmental changes in all cases. We average the data over the last 20 environmental changes. We study how the frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen, and the severity of environmental change, p, affect the evolvability of the protein sequences. A schematic diagram showing the molecular evolution of our protein system can be seen in Fig. 1.

Fig. 1.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 1.

Schematic diagram showing the evolution of the protein system.

Selection for Evolvability

Shown in Fig. 2 are the steady-state values of p swap and n mut that our protein system selects as a function of imposed frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen, and severity of environmental change, p. The DNA swapping moves that we propose have a high capacity for evolutionary change, because a significant number of amino acids may be altered in a protein sequence in one swap move. It is clear that our systems select for higher probabilities of DNA swapping moves, and thus evolvability, as the frequency and severity of environmental change increases. We stress the importance of this result. Mainstream evolutionary theory does not recognize a need for the selection of evolvability. More generally, we see that only in the limit of little or no environmental change, p swap → 0, do large-scale changes tend to be disfavored. The role of base substitution in our evolving system is more complex. For more severe environmental changes and for higher frequencies of environmental change, the system depends more on DNA swapping than on point mutation to produce low-energy proteins. In these cases, because the protein must make large changes to its sequence to adapt to the environmental change, selection results in high values of p swap, with base substitution having only a small effect on the energy of the protein. For less severe environmental changes and lower frequencies of environmental change, base substitution is sufficient to achieve the small modifications in protein sequence that are required for adaptation to the environmental change. Thus, we observe the higher dependence on n mut and lower dependence on p swap for small p. In addition, as 1/N gen → 0, n mut → 0, because mutations tend to be deleterious in stable systems with no environmental fluctuations.

Fig. 2.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 2.

n mut (dashed lines) and p swap (solid lines) as a function of the frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen, for different values of the severity of environmental change, p. The statistical errors in the results are smaller than the symbols on the figure.

Evolvability is intimately related to the diversity of a population. At short times, evolvability can be quantified by the diffusion coefficient in protein sequence space, D 0, which is given by the combined diffusion due to swapping of the subdomains and the point mutation of individual amino acids (61): Math The overwhelming contribution to D 0 comes from the swapping step, because the swapping move far more dramatically changes the sequence. The short-time diffusion rate selected for reflects, as a function of environmental change, a balance between staying within a favorable basin of attraction, or niche, and adaptation to a newly created, superior niche. As Fig. 2 shows, greater environmental change favors greater local diffusion, as indicated by the monotonic increase of p swap with p.

It is useful to regard base substitution as a means of fine tuning the protein sequences, whereas DNA swapping can be considered a source of more substantial evolutionary change. This hierarchy within the space of evolutionary moves becomes more apparent when studying the difference between starting and ending protein sequences within one environment as a function of p, p swap, and n mut. The distance between protein sequences is characterized by the Hamming distance between the respective amino acid sequences. For a given p, the Hamming distance decreases only slightly as the frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen, increases, but it has a very strong dependence on the severity of the environmental change, p, as shown in Fig. 3a . The sensitivity of the Hamming distance also shows markedly different behavior to p swap and n mut, as shown in Fig. 3b . For state points with fixed n mut, 1/N gen, and p, the Hamming distance strongly depends on the value of p swap. However, for state points with fixed p swap, 1/N gen, and p, the Hamming distance displays little or no variation with n mut. The Hamming distance is a long-time measure of the evolvability of the system. The long-time diffusion coefficient can be defined as the square of the Hamming distance multiplied by the frequency of environmental change. As Fig. 3a implies, the long-time evolvability, as measured by the long-time diffusion coefficient, increases with both the severity and frequency of environmental change.

Fig. 3.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 3.

Hamming distance and average variance. (a) Hamming distance as a function of the severity of environmental change, p, for the state points shown in Fig. 2. (b) Hamming distance as a function of n mut (dashed lines) and p swap (solid lines) for fixed N gen = 15 and for different severities of environmental change, p. In displaying the Hamming distance dependence on n mut (p swap), we fix p swap (n mut) to the selected values from Fig. 2. The selected values of n mut and p swap at each state point are shown by light and dark circles, respectively. (c) Average variance, σ2 U end, of the energy of a population at the end of an evolution, U end, as a function of the severity of environmental change, p, for different frequencies of environmental change, 1/N gen.

Due to the roughness of viability as a function of sequence, the exploration performed by any particular individual is limited to a local basin of attraction defined by the short-time mutation rates, and thus more independent traces through sequence space allow for more thorough evolution. In other words, the more diverse the starting population of individuals, the greater potential there is for evolution. Fig. 3c shows the average variance of the energy values at the end of the dynamics within a single instance of the environment as a function of the severity and frequency of environmental change. It is clear that the diversity increases monotonically with p and 1/N gen.

As we have seen, evolvability is quantifiable at any point in time through measurement of diversity and the local mutation rates. For this reason, causality does not prevent selection for evolvability. Because evolvability is an observable property, it can be selected for.

Susceptibility

A further measure of long-time evolvability is the response, or susceptibility, of the system to environmental change. In Fig. 4a we plot the average energy at the start, 〈U〉start, and end, 〈U〉end, of the dynamics within a single instance of the environment. This quantity is shown as a function of the severity, p, and frequency, 1/N gen, of environmental change. It is apparent that at low frequencies of environmental change, populations with greater diversity and variation, which are more evolvable, have slightly lower values of 〈U〉end. There is also a clear increasing trend in 〈U〉start as a function of p, which is a feature of the generalized NK model. Considering the ending energy of a protein molecule within one instance of the environment to be roughly the sum of n Gaussian terms from the generalized NK model, Math The starting energy of this protein molecule after an environmental change is given by Math where Math and where Math are random Gaussian variables with zero mean (Math = 0), whereas x i are evolved variables that are better than random and typically negative. Thus, the average starting energy of this protein molecule is Math Thus, averaging over the values in the new environment Math or, averaging over many environmental changes Math

Fig. 4.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 4.

Average energy, average change in energy, and probability distribution. (a) Average energy immediately after, 〈U〉start, and immediately before, 〈U〉end, an environmental change as a function of the severity of environmental change, p, for different frequencies of environmental change. (b) Average change in energy, 〈ΔU〉, multiplied by the frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen, as a function of the severity of environmental change, p. (c) Probability distribution of the susceptibility for different values of the severity of environmental change, p, for a fixed frequency of environmental change, 1/N gen = 0.1.

This average reduction in the energy is a measure of the susceptibility of a system, 〈ΔU〉/N gen = (〈U〉end – 〈U〉start)/N gen. In Fig. 4b we plot the susceptibility of our system as a function of the severity of environmental change, p. For a fixed frequency of environmental change, the susceptibility is a linear function of the severity of environmental change, as in Eq. 11. This simple analysis captures the essence of the dynamics that occurs in the correlated, generalized NK model. Fig. 4c shows that the probability distribution of the susceptibility is Gaussian in shape. Note also that the variance of the susceptibility increases with p in Fig. 4c , and thus the linearity of the susceptibility in Fig. 4b is not simply the result of a generalized fluctuation–dissipation theorem.

Implications for Evolution

Our results have implications for evolutionary theory. In our model system, populations of protein molecules that are subject to greater environmental change select for higher rates of evolvability. The selection criterion that we use is not a measure of evolvability in any way, yet the system selects for evolvability based on the implicit energetic benefits of adaptation to environmental change. In addition, there is no reason to assume that selection is optimal. In fact, systems optimal for one environment tend to have too little evolvability and tend to be selected against when faced with the inevitability of change.

Given our results, we propose that it is not mere chance that highly evolvable species tend to be found in rapidly changing environments or that an environmental crisis can trigger an increase in the rate of the evolution of a species. Indeed, selection for evolvability allows for the explanation of many data: the existence of somatic hypermutation in the immune system (13, 14, 16, 17), the evolution of drug resistance in species of bacteria (8, 30), and the occurrence and success of transpositional events in bacterial evolution (10, 31, 36). A recently studied example from mammals is the San Nicolas Island fox, which is a highly endangered species and the most monomorphic sexually reproducing animal known. This species, however, is found to have high levels of genetic variation within the major histocompatibility complex loci (62) that allows for increased pathogen resistance.

We believe that our results are of relevance to the field of vaccine and drug design. Currently, the design of new vaccines and drugs is largely based on the assumption that pathogens evolve by local space searching in response to therapeutic and immune selection. However, it is clear that we must anticipate the evolutionary potential of large DNA swapping events in the development of viruses, parasites, bacteria, and cancers if we are to engineer effective methods of treating them. How evolvability correlates with treatment strategy, and how to drive pathogens into regions of low evolvability where they are eradicated most easily, is of importance to efforts for vaccine and drug engineering.

Specific pathogenic examples of evolvability include the emergence of new influenza strains by a novel hemagglutinin neuraminidase recombination, followed by antigenic drift to a highly infectious strain (23); emergence of many new HIV strains with the spread of the disease from its site of origin in Africa (63, 64); and the increased emergence of new infectious diseases associated with modern, post-World War II travel (65). Additionally, a recent study of the dynamics of HIV-1 recombination suggests that HIV-1 may have evolved high recombination rates to foster rapid diversification and further its survival (66).

Note that evolvability is not simply the observation that new strains occur; rather, it is the underlying probability with which new strains are created by genetic modification. These new strains may proliferate and be observed, or they may fail and not be observed to an appreciable extent. Fundamental study of evolvability, then, requires an appreciation of these underlying rates of genetic change. These underlying rates, such as polymerase error rates, recombination rates, and transposition rates, are what selection for increased evolvability may modulate (67). These underlying rates of change are inheritable and can be altered by mutation. Study of these rates of genetic change, deconvoluted from observed rates of evolution, which are these rates multiplied by a probability of survival, is of fundamental interest.

It is intriguing that we find that at low frequencies of environmental change, populations that are subject to more severe environmental changes can produce lower-energy individuals than populations that are not subject to environmental changes (Fig. 4a ). Thus, under some conditions, adaptability can provide global benefits. This finding can be contrasted to the more customary expectation that specialists are better than generalists (68). In experimental studies of Chlamydomonas, generalists that were evolved in alternating light and dark conditions were found to be better than their ancestors in both light and dark conditions but less good than specialists that had evolved exclusively in one of the environmental conditions (69). Studies of the evolution of E. coli at constant and alternating temperatures produced similar results (70, 71). The nature of the environmental change in these studies is not completely random as in our model. In addition, the number of rounds of selected evolution under each environmental condition is perhaps better defined within our model. These experiments do point to possible tests of our theory. For a species that is capable of DNA swapping evolutionary moves, a systematic study of competency as a function of the frequency of a random environmental change would be of interest. We predict that under some conditions, certain frequencies of environmental change will produce better individuals, after a given number of rounds of evolution and selection, than would be produced by evolution in a constant environment. Different severities of environmental change could also be imposed by altering the change in environmental variables between samples, such as temperature, food concentrations, light conditions, and exposure to disease. With regard to susceptibility, we would expect the rate of change of viability within an environment to be higher in systems with more frequent and harsher environmental changes because of greater evolvability.

Summary

Not only has life evolved, but life has evolved to evolve. That is, correlations within protein structure have evolved, and mechanisms to manipulate these correlations have evolved in tandem. The rates at which the various events within the hierarchy of evolutionary moves occur are not random or arbitrary but are selected by Darwinian evolution. Sensibly, rapid or extreme environmental change leads to selection for greater evolvability. This selection is not forbidden by causality and is strongest on the largest-scale moves within the mutational hierarchy.

Many observations within evolutionary biology, heretofore considered evolutionary happenstance or accidents, are explained by selection for evolvability. For example, the vertebrate immune system shows that the variable environment of antigens has provided selective pressure for the use of adaptable codons and low-fidelity polymerases during somatic hypermutation. A similar driving force for biased codon usage as a result of productively high mutation rates is observed in the hemagglutinin protein of influenza A. Selection for evolvability explains the prevalence of transposons among bacteria and recombination among higher organisms. We suggest that therapeutics also confer selective pressure on the evolvability of pathogens, and that this driving force for antigenic drift should be considered in drug- and vaccine-design efforts.

Acknowledgments

We thank Kevin R. Foster for a careful reading of the manuscript. This research is supported by the National Institutes of Health.

Footnotes

  • ↵ * To whom correspondence should be addressed at: Department of Bioengineering and Department of Physics and Astronomy, MS 142, Rice University, 6100 Main Street, Houston, TX 77005-1892. E-mail: mwdeem{at}chinook.rice.edu.

  • Freely available online through the PNAS open access option.

  • Copyright © 2004, The National Academy of Sciences

References

  1. ↵
    Gould, S. J. (1983) Hen's Teeth and Horse's Toes (Norton, New York).
  2. ↵
    Kirschner, M. & Gerhart, J. (1998) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 95 , 8420–8427. pmid:9671692
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  3. Dawkins, R. (1989) in Artificial Life, ed. Langton, C. G. (Addison–Wesley, New York), pp. 201–220.
  4. ↵
    Radman, M., Matic, I. & Taddei, F. (1999) Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 870 , 146–155. pmid:10415480
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  5. ↵
    Chicurel, M. (2001) Science 292 , 1824–1827. pmid:11397928
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  6. ↵
    Partridge, L. & Barton, N. H. (2000) Nature 407 , 457–458. pmid:11028981
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  7. ↵
    Kidwell, M. G. (1997) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 94 , 7704–7711. pmid:9223252
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  8. ↵
    Shapiro, J. A. (1997) Trends Genet. 13 , 98–104. pmid:9066268
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  9. ↵
    Barton, N. H. & Charlesworth, B. (1998) Science 281 , 1986–1990. pmid:9748151
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  10. ↵
    Fedoroff, N. (2000) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 97 , 7002–7007. pmid:10860963
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  11. Shapiro, J. A. (2002) J. Biol. Phys. 28 , 745–764.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  12. ↵
    Shapiro, J. A. (2002) Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 981 , 111–134. pmid:12547677
    OpenUrlPubMed
  13. ↵
    Storb, U. (2001) Nat. Immunol. 2 , 484–485. pmid:11376332
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  14. ↵
    Plotkin, J. B. & Dushoff, J. (2003) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 100 , 7152–7157. pmid:12748378
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  15. ↵
    Caporale, L. H. (2003) Am. Sci. 91 , 234–241.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  16. ↵
    Kepler, T. B. (1997) Mol. Biol. Evol. 14 , 637–643. pmid:9190065
    OpenUrlAbstract
  17. ↵
    Friedberg, E. C., Feaver, W. F. & Gerlach, V. L. (2000) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 97 , 5681–5683. pmid:10811923
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  18. ↵
    Freire, E. (2002) Nat. Biotechnol. 20 , 15–16. pmid:11753347
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  19. ↵
    Kepler, T. B. & Perelson, A. S. (1998) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 95 , 11514–11519. pmid:9751697
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  20. ↵
    Rosenberg, S. M. (2001) Nat. Rev. Genet. 2 , 504–515. pmid:11433357
    OpenUrlPubMed
  21. ↵
    Pepper, J. W. (2003) BioSystems 69 , 115–126. pmid:12689725
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  22. ↵
    Colegrave, N. (2002) Nature 420 , 664–666. pmid:12478292
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  23. ↵
    Frank, S. A. (2002) Immunology and Evolution of Infectious Disease (Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton).
  24. ↵
    Wagner, G. P. & Altenberg, L. (1996) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 50 , 967–976.
    OpenUrl
  25. Lenski, R. E., Ofria, C., Pennock, R. T. & Adami, C. (2003) Nature 423 , 139–144. pmid:12736677
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  26. Blasio, F. V. D. (1999) Phys. Rev. E 60 , 5912–5917.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  27. Travis, J. M. J. & Travis, E. R. (2002) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 269 , 591–597.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  28. Siegal, M. L. & Bergman, A. (2002) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 99 , 10528–10532. pmid:12082173
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  29. ↵
    Bergman, A. & Siegal, M. L. (2003) Nature 424 , 549–552. pmid:12891357
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  30. ↵
    Shapiro, J. A. (1992) Genetica 86 , 99–111. pmid:1334920
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  31. ↵
    Lawrence, J. G. (1997) Trends Microbiol. 5 , 355–359. pmid:9294891
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  32. ↵
    Zhang, Y.-X., Perry, K., Vinci, V. A., Powell, K., Stemmer, W. P. C. & del Cardayre, S. B. (2002) Nature 415 , 644–646. pmid:11832946
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  33. ↵
    Pennisi, E. (1998) Science 281 , 1131–1134. pmid:9735027
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  34. Gilbert, W. (1978) Nature 271 , 501. pmid:622185
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  35. Gilbert, W., DeSouza, S. J. & Long, M. (1997) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 94 , 7698–7703. pmid:9223251
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  36. ↵
    Duret, L., Marais, G. & Biemont, C. (2000) Genetics 156 , 1661–1669. pmid:11102365
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  37. Lonnig, W.-E. & Saedler, H. (2002) Annu. Rev. Genet. 36 , 389–410. pmid:12429698
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  38. Levin, B. R. & Bergstrom, C. T. (2000) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 97 , 6981–6985. pmid:10860960
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  39. ↵
    Doolittle, W. F. (2000) Sci. Am. 282 (2), 90–95. pmid:10710791
    OpenUrlPubMed
  40. ↵
    Stemmer, W. P. C. (1994) Nature 370 , 389–391. pmid:8047147
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  41. Crameri, A., Raillard, S. A., Bermudez, E. & Stemmer, W. P. C. (1998) Nature 391 , 288–291. pmid:9440693
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  42. Zhang, J.-H., Dawes, G. & Stemmer, W. P. C. (1997) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 94 , 4504–4509. pmid:9114019
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  43. Moore, J. C., Jin, H.-M., Kuchner, O. & Arnold, F. H. (1997) J. Mol. Evol. 272 , 336–347.
    OpenUrl
  44. ↵
    Lutz, S. & Benkovic, S. J. (2000) Curr. Opin. Biotechnol. 11 , 319–324. pmid:10975450
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  45. ↵
    Clarke, B. C. (1979) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 205 , 453–474. pmid:42055
    OpenUrlPubMed
  46. Dawkins, R. & Krebs, J. R. (1979) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 205 , 489–512. pmid:42057
    OpenUrlPubMed
  47. ↵
    Gould, S. J. & Lewontin, R. C. (1979) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 205 , 581–598. pmid:42062
    OpenUrlPubMed
  48. ↵
    Gillespie, J. H. (1991) The Causes of Molecular Evolution (Oxford Univ. Press, Oxford).
  49. ↵
    Frank, S. A. & Slatkin, M. (1990) Am. Nat. 136 , 244–260.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  50. ↵
    Smith, J. M. (1979) Proc. R. Soc. London Ser. B 205 , 475–488. pmid:42056
    OpenUrlPubMed
  51. Smith, J. M. (1982) Evolution and the Theory of Games (Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, U.K.).
  52. ↵
    Sasaki, A. & Ellner, S. (1995) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 49 , 337–350.
    OpenUrl
  53. ↵
    Sato, K., Ito, Y., Yomo, T. & Kaneko, K. (2003) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 100 , 14086–14090. pmid:14615583
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  54. ↵
    Bogarad, L. D. & Deem, M. W. (1999) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 96 , 2591–2595. pmid:10077554
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  55. ↵
    Kauffman, S. & Levin, S. (1987) J. Theor. Biol. 128 , 11–45. pmid:3431131
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  56. Kauffman, S. A. (1993) The Origins of Order (Oxford Univ. Press, New York).
  57. ↵
    Kauffman, S. A. & MacReady, W. G. (1995) J. Theor. Biol. 173 , 427–440. pmid:7783452
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  58. ↵
    Perelson, A. S. & Macken, C. A. (1995) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 92 , 9657–9661. pmid:7568192
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  59. ↵
    Deem, M. W. & Lee, H. Y. (2003) Phys. Rev. Lett. 91 , 068101. pmid:12935112
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  60. ↵
    Michod, R. E. & Levin, B. R., eds. (1988) The Evolution of Sex (Sinauer, Sunderland, MA).
  61. ↵
    Chandrasekhar, S. (1943) Rev. Mod. Phys. 15 , 1–89.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  62. ↵
    Aguilar, A., Roemer, G., Debenham, S., Binns, M., Garcelon, D. & Wayne, R. K. (2004) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101 , 3490–3494. pmid:14990802
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  63. ↵
    Zhu, T. F., Korber, B. T., Nahmias, A. J., Hooper, E., Sharp, P. M. & Ho, D. D. (1998) Nature 391 , 594–597. pmid:9468138
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  64. ↵
    Gao, F., Bailes, E., Robertson, D. L., Chen, Y. L., Rodenburg, C. M., Michael, S. F., Cummins, L. B., Arthur, L. O., Peeters, M., Shaw, G. M., et al. (1999) Nature 397 , 436–441. pmid:9989410
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  65. ↵
    Lederberg, J., Shope, R. E. & S. C. Oaks, J., eds. (1992) Emerging Infections: Microbial Threats to Health in the United States (Natl. Acad. Press, Washington, DC).
  66. ↵
    Levy, D. N., Aldrovandi, G. M., Kutsch, O. & Shaw, G. M. (2004) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 101 , 4204–4209. pmid:15010526
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  67. ↵
    Tan, T., Bogarad, L. D. & Deem, M. W. (2004) J. Mol. Evol., in press.
  68. ↵
    Elena, S. F. & Lenski, R. E. (2003) Nat. Rev. Genet. 4 , 457–469. pmid:12776215
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  69. ↵
    Reboud, X. & Bell, G. (1997) Heredity 78 , 507–514.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  70. ↵
    Bennett, A. F. & Lenski, R. E. (1993) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 47 , 1–12.
  71. ↵
    Leroi, A. M., Lenski, R. E. & Bennett, A. F. (1994) Evolution (Lawrence, Kans.) 48 , 1222–1229.
    OpenUrl
View Abstract
PreviousNext
Back to top
Article Alerts
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on PNAS.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Evolvability is a selectable trait
(Your Name) has sent you a message from PNAS
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the PNAS web site.
Citation Tools
Evolvability is a selectable trait
David J. Earl, Michael W. Deem
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Aug 2004, 101 (32) 11531-11536; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.0404656101

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Request Permissions
Share
Evolvability is a selectable trait
David J. Earl, Michael W. Deem
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Aug 2004, 101 (32) 11531-11536; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.0404656101
del.icio.us logo Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo CiteULike logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Mendeley logo Mendeley
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences: 116 (7)
Current Issue

Submit

Sign up for Article Alerts

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • The Generalized Block NK Model
    • System Evolution and Environmental Change
    • Selection for Evolvability
    • Susceptibility
    • Implications for Evolution
    • Summary
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

You May Also be Interested in

Several aspects of the proposal, which aims to expand open access, require serious discussion and, in some cases, a rethink.
Opinion: “Plan S” falls short for society publishers—and for the researchers they serve
Several aspects of the proposal, which aims to expand open access, require serious discussion and, in some cases, a rethink.
Image credit: Dave Cutler (artist).
Several large or long-lived animals seem strangely resistant to developing cancer. Elucidating the reasons why could lead to promising cancer-fighting strategies in humans.
Core Concept: Solving Peto’s Paradox to better understand cancer
Several large or long-lived animals seem strangely resistant to developing cancer. Elucidating the reasons why could lead to promising cancer-fighting strategies in humans.
Image credit: Shutterstock.com/ronnybas frimages.
Featured Profile
PNAS Profile of NAS member and biochemist Hao Wu
 Nonmonogamous strawberry poison frog (Oophaga pumilio).  Image courtesy of Yusan Yang (University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh).
Putative signature of monogamy
A study suggests a putative gene-expression hallmark common to monogamous male vertebrates of some species, namely cichlid fishes, dendrobatid frogs, passeroid songbirds, common voles, and deer mice, and identifies 24 candidate genes potentially associated with monogamy.
Image courtesy of Yusan Yang (University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh).
Active lifestyles. Image courtesy of Pixabay/MabelAmber.
Meaningful life tied to healthy aging
Physical and social well-being in old age are linked to self-assessments of life worth, and a spectrum of behavioral, economic, health, and social variables may influence whether aging individuals believe they are leading meaningful lives.
Image courtesy of Pixabay/MabelAmber.

More Articles of This Classification

Physical Sciences

  • Deep elastic strain engineering of bandgap through machine learning
  • Single-molecule excitation–emission spectroscopy
  • Microscopic description of acid–base equilibrium
Show more

Physics

  • Unraveling materials Berry curvature and Chern numbers from real-time evolution of Bloch states
  • Opinion: “Plan S” falls short for society publishers—and for the researchers they serve
  • Limits of multifunctionality in tunable networks
Show more

Biological Sciences

  • Structural basis for activity of TRIC counter-ion channels in calcium release
  • PGC1A regulates the IRS1:IRS2 ratio during fasting to influence hepatic metabolism downstream of insulin
  • Altered neural odometry in the vertical dimension
Show more

Evolution

  • Molecular mechanism and history of non-sense to sense evolution of antifreeze glycoprotein gene in northern gadids
  • Transitions between foot postures are associated with elevated rates of body size evolution in mammals
  • Hagfish from the Cretaceous Tethys Sea and a reconciliation of the morphological–molecular conflict in early vertebrate phylogeny
Show more

Related Content

  • No related articles found.
  • Scopus
  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited by...

  • Increasing mutation rate of local adaptation during range expansion
  • Something Old, Something New: Conserved Enzymes and the Evolution of Novelty in Plant Specialized Metabolism
  • Primordial germ cells: the first cell lineage or the last cells standing?
  • The Remarkable Pliability and Promiscuity of Specialized Metabolism
  • Comparative Genome Biology of a Serogroup B Carriage and Disease Strain Supports a Polygenic Nature of Meningococcal Virulence
  • Protein Dynamism and Evolvability
  • Emergence of species in evolutionary "simulated annealing"
  • The Frequency of Fitness Peak Shifts Is Increased at Expanding Range Margins Due to Mutation Surfing
  • Varying environments can speed up evolution
  • The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity
  • Complete and SOS-Mediated Response of Staphylococcus aureus to the Antibiotic Ciprofloxacin
  • Protein stability promotes evolvability
  • Suppression of viral infectivity through lethal defection
  • Scopus (162)
  • Google Scholar

Similar Articles

Site Logo
Powered by HighWire
  • Submit Manuscript
  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • RSS Feeds
  • Email Alerts

Articles

  • Current Issue
  • Latest Articles
  • Archive

PNAS Portals

  • Classics
  • Front Matter
  • Teaching Resources
  • Anthropology
  • Chemistry
  • Physics
  • Sustainability Science

Information

  • Authors
  • Editorial Board
  • Reviewers
  • Press
  • Site Map

Feedback    Privacy/Legal

Copyright © 2019 National Academy of Sciences. Online ISSN 1091-6490