Skip to main content
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Accessibility Statement
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian
  • Log in
  • My Cart

Main menu

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Accessibility Statement
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian

User menu

  • Log in
  • My Cart

Search

  • Advanced search
Home
Home

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses

New Research In

Physical Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Physics
  • Chemistry
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Applied Mathematics
  • Applied Physical Sciences
  • Astronomy
  • Computer Sciences
  • Earth, Atmospheric, and Planetary Sciences
  • Engineering
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Mathematics
  • Statistics

Social Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Economic Sciences
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Political Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Social Sciences

Biological Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Agricultural Sciences
  • Anthropology
  • Applied Biological Sciences
  • Biochemistry
  • Biophysics and Computational Biology
  • Cell Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Evolution
  • Genetics
  • Immunology and Inflammation
  • Medical Sciences
  • Microbiology
  • Neuroscience
  • Pharmacology
  • Physiology
  • Plant Biology
  • Population Biology
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Sustainability Science
  • Systems Biology
Opinion

Opinion: Why science needs philosophy

Lucie Laplane, Paolo Mantovani, Ralph Adolphs, Hasok Chang, Alberto Mantovani, Margaret McFall-Ngai, Carlo Rovelli, Elliott Sober, and Thomas Pradeu
PNAS March 5, 2019 116 (10) 3948-3952; https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1900357116
Lucie Laplane
aInstitut d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences et des techniques (UMR8590), CNRS & Panthéon-Sorbonne University, 75006 Paris, France;
bNormal and Pathological Hematopoiesis (UMR1170), Gustave Roussy Cancer Campus, 94800 Villejuif, France;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Paolo Mantovani
cDepartment of Humanities, University of Roehampton, London, SW15 5PJ, United Kingdom;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Ralph Adolphs
dDivision of Humanities and Social Sciences, Caltech, Pasadena, CA 91125;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Hasok Chang
eDepartment of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Cambridge, Cambridge CB2 3RH, United Kingdom;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Alberto Mantovani
fDepartment of Biomedical Sciences, Humanitas University and Istituto Clinico Humanitas, 20090 Milan, Italy;
gWilliam Harvey Research Institute, Queen Mary University, London EC1M 6BQ, United Kingdom;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Margaret McFall-Ngai
hPacific Biosciences Research Center, School of Ocean and Earth Science and Technology, University of Hawai‘i at Mānoa, Honolulu, HI 96822;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Carlo Rovelli
iCentre de Physique Theorique de Luminy (UMR 7332), CNRS, Aix-Marseille-University, University of Toulon, 13288 Marseille Cedex 9, France;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Elliott Sober
jPhilosophy Department, University of Wisconsin–Madison, Madison, WI 53706;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Thomas Pradeu
aInstitut d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences et des techniques (UMR8590), CNRS & Panthéon-Sorbonne University, 75006 Paris, France;
kImmunoConcept (UMR5164), CNRS & University of Bordeaux, 33076 Bordeaux Cedex, France
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • For correspondence: thomas.pradeu@u-bordeaux.fr
  • Article
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

A knowledge of the historic and philosophical background gives that kind of independence from prejudices of his generation from which most scientists are suffering. This independence created by philosophical insight is—in my opinion—the mark of distinction between a mere artisan or specialist and a real seeker after truth.

Albert Einstein, Letter to Robert Thornton, 1944

Despite the tight historical links between science and philosophy, present-day scientists often perceive philosophy as completely different from, and even antagonistic to, science. We argue here that, to the contrary, philosophy can have an important and productive impact on science.

Figure1
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint

Despite the tight historical links between science and philosophy, hearkening back to Plato, Aristotle, and others (here evoked with Raphael’s famous School of Athens), present-day scientists often perceive philosophy as completely different from, and even antagonistic to, science. To the contrary, we believe philosophy can have an important and productive impact on science. Image credit: Shutterstock.com/Isogood_patrick.

We illustrate our point with three examples taken from various fields of the contemporary life sciences. Each bears on cutting-edge scientific research, and each has been explicitly acknowledged by practicing researchers as a useful contribution to science. These and other examples show that philosophy’s contribution can take at least four forms: the clarification of scientific concepts, the critical assessment of scientific assumptions or methods, the formulation of new concepts and theories, and the fostering of dialogue between different sciences, as well as between science and society.

Conceptual Clarification and Stem Cells.

First, philosophy offers conceptual clarification. Conceptual clarifications not only improve the precision and utility of scientific terms but also lead to novel experimental investigations because the choice of a given conceptual framework strongly constrains how experiments are conceived.

The definition of stem cells is a prime example. Philosophy has a long tradition of investigating properties, and the tools in use in this tradition have recently been applied to describe “stemness,” the property that defines stem cells. One of us has shown that four different kinds of properties exist under the guise of stemness in current scientific knowledge (1). Depending on the type of tissue, stemness can be a categorical property (an intrinsic property of the stem cell, independent of its environment), a dispositional property (an intrinsic property of the stem cell that is controlled by the microenvironment), a relational property (an extrinsic property that can be conferred to non–stem cells by the microenvironment), or a systemic property (a property that is maintained and controlled at the level of the entire cell population).

Stem cell and cancer biology researcher Hans Clevers notes that this philosophical analysis highlights important semantic and conceptual problems in oncology and stem cell biology; he also suggests this analysis is readily applicable to experimentation (2). Indeed, beyond conceptual clarification, this philosophical work has real-world applications as illustrated by the case of cancer stem cells in oncology.

Research aimed at developing drugs targeting either the cancer stem cells or their microenvironment actually rely on different kinds of stemness and are thus likely to have different rates of success depending on cancer type (1). Moreover, they might not cover all cancer types because current therapeutic strategies do not take into account the systemic definition of stemness. Determining the kind of stemness found in each tissue and cancer is thus useful to direct the development and choice of anticancer therapies. In practice, this framework has led to the investigation of cancer therapies that combine the targeting of intrinsic cancer stem cell properties, their microenvironment, and immune checkpoints to cover all possible kinds of stemness (3).

Furthermore, this philosophical framework recently has been applied to another field, the study of organoids. In a systemic review of experimental data on organoids from various sources, Picollet-D’hahan et al. (4) characterized the ability to form organoids as a dispositional property. They could then argue that to increase the efficiency and reproducibility of organoid production, a major current challenge in the field, researchers need a better understanding of the intrinsic part of the dispositional property that is influenced by the microenvironment. To discriminate the intrinsic features of cells that have such a disposition, this group is now developing high-throughput functional genomic methods, enabling an investigation of the role of virtually every human gene in organoid formation.

Immunogenicity and the Microbiome.

Complementary to its role in conceptual clarification, philosophy can contribute to the critique of scientific assumptions—and can even be proactive in formulating novel, testable, and predictive theories that help set new paths for empirical research.

For example, a philosophical critique of the immune self–nonself framework (5) has led to two significant scientific contributions. First, it was the basis of the formulation of a novel theoretical framework, the discontinuity theory of immunity, which complements previous self–nonself and danger models by proposing that the immune system responds to sudden modifications of antigenic motifs (6). This theory sheds light on many important immunological phenomena, including autoimmune disease, immune responses to tumors, and immunological tolerance to chronically expressed ligands. The discontinuity theory has been applied to a multitude of questions, helping explore the effects of chemotherapeutic agents on immunomodulation in cancer and spelling out how natural killer cells constantly modify their phenotype and functions through their interactions with their ligands in a way that ensures tolerance to bodily (self) constituents (7). The theory also helps explain the consequences of repeated vaccinations in immunocompromised individuals (8) and suggests dynamic mathematical models of immune activation. Collectively, these various empirical assessments illustrate how philosophically inspired proposals can lead to novel experiments, opening up new avenues for research.

Second, the philosophical critique contributed along with other philosophical approaches to the notion that every organism, far from being a genetically homogenous self, is a symbiotic community harboring and tolerating multiple foreign elements (including bacteria and viruses), which are recognized but not eliminated by its immune system (9). Research on symbiotic integration and immune tolerance has far-reaching consequences for our conception of what constitutes an individual organism, which is increasingly conceptualized as a complex ecosystem whose key functions, from development to defense, repair, and cognition, are affected by interactions with microbes (9).

Influencing Cognitive Science.

The study of cognition and cognitive neuroscience offers a striking illustration of the deep and long-lasting influence of philosophy on science. As with immunology, philosophers have formulated influential theories and experiments, helped initiate specific research programs, and contributed to paradigm shifts. But the scale of the influence dwarfs the immunology case. Philosophy had a part in the move from behaviorism to cognitivism and computationalism in the 1960s. Perhaps most visible has been the theory of the modularity of mind, proposed by philosopher Jerry Fodor (10). Its influence on theories of cognitive architecture can hardly be overstated. In a tribute after Fodor’s passing in 2017, leading cognitive psychologist James Russell spoke in the magazine of the British Psychological Society of “cognitive developmental psychology BF (before Fodor) and AF (after Fodor)” (https://thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/jerry-fodor-1935-2017).

Modularity refers to the idea that mental phenomena arise from the operation of multiple distinct processes, not from a single undifferentiated one. Inspired by evidence in experimental psychology, by Chomskian linguistics, and by new computational theories in philosophy of mind, Fodor theorized that human cognition is structured in a set of lower-level, domain-specific, informationally encapsulated specialized modules and a higher-level, domain-general central system for abductive reasoning with information only flowing upward vertically, not downward or horizontally (i.e., between modules). He also formulated stringent criteria for modularity. To this day, Fodor’s proposal sets the terms for much empirical research and theory in many areas of cognitive science and neuroscience (11, 12), including cognitive development, evolutionary psychology, artificial intelligence, and cognitive anthropology. Although his theory has been revised and challenged, researchers continue to use, tweak, and debate his approach and basic conceptual toolkit.

Philosophy and science share the tools of logic, conceptual analysis, and rigorous argumentation. Yet philosophers can operate these tools with degrees of thoroughness, freedom, and theoretical abstraction that practicing researchers often cannot afford in their daily activities.

The false-belief task constitutes another key instance of philosophy’s impact on the cognitive sciences. Philosopher Daniel Dennett was the first to conceive the basic logic of this experiment as a revision of a test used for evaluating theory of mind, the ability to attribute mental states to oneself and others (13). The task tests the capacity to attribute others with beliefs that one considers false, the key idea being that reasoning about others’ false beliefs, as opposed to true beliefs, requires conceiving of other people as having mental representations that diverge from one’s own and from the way the world actually is. Its first empirical application was in 1983 (14), in an article whose title, “Beliefs About Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children’s Understanding of Deception,” is in itself a direct tribute to Dennett’s contribution.

The false-belief task represents a milestone experiment in various areas of cognitive science and neuroscience, with wide application and implications. They include testing for cognitive developmental stages in children, debating the architecture of human cognition and its distinct capacities, assessing theory of mind abilities in great apes, developing theories of autism as mind blindness (according to which difficulties in passing the false-belief task are associated with the condition), and determining which particular brain regions are associated with the capacity to reason about the contents of another person’s mind (15).

Philosophy has also helped the field of cognitive science winnow problematic or outdated assumptions, helping drive scientific change. The concepts of mind, intelligence, consciousness, and emotion are used ubiquitously across different fields with often little agreement on their meaning (16). Engineering artificial intelligence, constructing psychological theories of mental state variables, and using neuroscience tools to investigate consciousness and emotion require the conceptual tools for self-critique and cross-disciplinary dialogue—precisely the tools that philosophy can supply.

Figure2
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint

Philosophy—sometimes represented with the Greek letter phi—can help advance all levels of the scientific enterprise, from theory to experiment. Recent examples include contributions to stem cell biology, immunology, symbiosis, and cognitive science. Image credit: Wiebke Bretting (artist).

Philosophy and Scientific Knowledge.

The above examples are far from the only ones: in the life sciences, philosophical reflection has played an important role in issues as diverse as evolutionary altruism (17), debate over units of selection (18), the construction of a “tree of life” (19), the predominance of microbes in the biosphere, the definition of the gene, and the critical examination of the concept of innateness (20). Likewise, in physics, fundamental questions such as the definition of time have been enriched by the work of philosophers. For example, the analysis of temporal irreversibility by Huw Price (21) and closed temporal curves by David Lewis (22) have helped dispel conceptual confusion in physics (23).

Inspired by these examples and many others, we see philosophy and science as located on a continuum. Philosophy and science share the tools of logic, conceptual analysis, and rigorous argumentation. Yet philosophers can operate these tools with degrees of thoroughness, freedom, and theoretical abstraction that practicing researchers often cannot afford in their daily activities. Philosophers with the relevant scientific knowledge can then contribute significantly to the advancement of science at all levels of the scientific enterprise from theory to experiment as the above examples show.

But how in practice can we facilitate cooperation between researchers and philosophers? At first sight, the solution might seem obvious: each community should make a step toward the other. Yet it would be a mistake to consider this an easy task. The obstacles are many. At present, a significant number of philosophers disdain science or don’t see the relevance of science to their work. Even among philosophers who favor dialogue with researchers, few have a good knowledge of the latest science. Conversely, few researchers perceive the benefits philosophical insights can bring. In the current scientific context, dominated by increasing specialization and growing demands for funding and output, only a very limited number of researchers have the time and opportunity to even be aware of the work produced by philosophers on science let alone to read it.

To overcome these difficulties, we believe that a series of simple recommendations, which could be readily implemented, can help bridge the gap between science and philosophy. The reconnection between philosophy and science is both highly desirable and more realizable in practice than suggested by the decades of estrangement between them.

  • i) Make more room for philosophy in scientific conferences. This is a very simple mechanism for researchers to assess the potential usefulness of philosophers’ insights for their own research. Reciprocally, more researchers could participate in philosophy conferences, expanding on the efforts of organizations such as the International Society for the History, Philosophy, and Social Studies of Biology; the Philosophy of Science Association; and the Society for Philosophy of Science in Practice.

  • ii) Host philosophers in scientific labs and departments. This is a powerful way (already explored by some of the authors and others) for philosophers to learn science and provide more appropriate and well-grounded analyses, and for researchers to benefit from philosophical inputs and acclimatize to philosophy more generally. This might be the most efficient way to help philosophy have a rapid and concrete impact on science.

  • iii) Co-supervise PhD students. The co-supervision of PhD students by a researcher and a philosopher is an excellent opportunity to make possible the cross-feeding of the two fields. It facilitates the production of dissertations that are both experimentally rich and conceptually rigorous, and in the process, it trains the next generation of philosopher-scientists.

  • iv) Create curricula balanced in science and philosophy that foster a genuine dialogue between them. Some such curricula already exist in some countries, but expanding them should be a high priority. They can provide students in science with a perspective that better empowers them for the conceptual challenges of modern science and provide philosophers with a solid basis for the scientific knowledge that will maximize their impact on science. Science curricula might include a class in the history of science and in the philosophy of science. Philosophy curricula might include a science module.

  • v) Read science and philosophy. Reading science is indispensable for the practice of philosophy of science, but reading philosophy can also constitute a great source of inspiration for researchers as illustrated by some of the examples above. For example, journal clubs where both science and philosophy contributions are discussed constitute an efficient way to integrate philosophy and science.

  • vi) Open new sections devoted to philosophical and conceptual issues in science journals. This strategy would be an appropriate and compelling way to suggest that the philosophical and conceptual work is continuous with the experimental work, in so far as it is inspired by it, and can inspire it in return. It would also make philosophical reflections about a particular scientific domain much more visible to the relevant scientific community than when they are published in philosophy journals, which are rarely read by scientists.

We hope that the practical steps set out above will encourage a renaissance in the integration of science and philosophy. Furthermore, we argue that maintaining a close allegiance with philosophy will enhance the vitality of science. Modern science without philosophy will run up against a wall: the deluge of data within each field will make interpretation more and more difficult, neglect of breadth and history will further splinter and separate scientific subdisciplines, and the emphasis on methods and empirical results will drive shallower and shallower training of students. As Carl Woese (24) wrote: “a society that permits biology to become an engineering discipline, that allows science to slip into the role of changing the living world without trying to understand it, is a danger to itself.” We need a reinvigoration of science at all levels, one that returns to us the benefits of close ties with philosophy.

Acknowledgments

T.P. has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme Grant 637647 – IDEM. M.M.-N. is funded by NIH Grants R37 AI050661 and R01 OD011024. R.A. is funded in part by NSF Grant BCS-1845958.

Footnotes

  • ↵1L.L. and P.M. contributed equally to this work.

  • ↵2To whom correspondence should be addressed. Email: thomas.pradeu{at}u-bordeaux.fr.
  • The authors declare no conflict of interest.

  • Any opinions, findings, conclusions, or recommendations expressed in this work are those of the authors and have not been endorsed by the National Academy of Sciences.

Published under the PNAS license.

View Abstract

References

  1. ↵
    1. Laplane L
    (2016) Cancer Stem Cells: Philosophy and Therapies (Harvard Univ Press, Cambridge, MA).
  2. ↵
    1. Clevers H
    (2016) Cancer therapy: Defining stemness. Nature 534:176–177.
    OpenUrl
  3. ↵
    1. Bialkowski L, et al.
    (2018) Immune checkpoint blockade combined with IL-6 and TGF-β inhibition improves the therapeutic outcome of mRNA-based immunotherapy. Int J Cancer 143:686–698.
    OpenUrl
  4. ↵
    1. Picollet-D’hahan N,
    2. Dolega ME,
    3. Freida D,
    4. Martin DK,
    5. Gidrol X
    (2017) Deciphering cell intrinsic properties: A key issue for robust organoid production. Trends Biotechnol 35:1035–1048.
    OpenUrl
  5. ↵
    1. Pradeu T,
    2. Carosella ED
    (2006) On the definition of a criterion of immunogenicity. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 103:17858–17861.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  6. ↵
    1. Pradeu T,
    2. Jaeger S,
    3. Vivier E
    (2013) The speed of change: Towards a discontinuity theory of immunity? Nat Rev Immunol 13:764–769.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  7. ↵
    1. Boudreau JE,
    2. Hsu KC
    (2018) Natural killer cell education and the response to infection and cancer therapy: Stay tuned. Trends Immunol 39:222–239.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  8. ↵
    1. Rinaldi S, et al.
    (2014) Antibody but not memory B-cell responses are tuned-down in vertically HIV-1 infected children and young individuals being vaccinated yearly against influenza. Vaccine 32:657–663.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  9. ↵
    1. McFall-Ngai M, et al.
    (2013) Animals in a bacterial world, a new imperative for the life sciences. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 110:3229–3236.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  10. ↵
    1. Fodor JA
    (1983) Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA).
  11. ↵
    1. Barrett HC,
    2. Kurzban R
    (2006) Modularity in cognition: Framing the debate. Psychol Rev 113:628–647.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  12. ↵
    1. Kanwisher N
    (2000) Domain specificity in face perception. Nat Neurosci 3:759–763.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. ↵
    1. Dennett DC
    (1978) Beliefs about beliefs. Behav Brain Sci 1:568–570.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  14. ↵
    1. Wimmer H,
    2. Perner J
    (1983) Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 13:103–128.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  15. ↵
    1. Frith U,
    2. Frith CD
    (2003) Development and neurophysiology of mentalizing. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 358:459–473.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  16. ↵
    1. Adolphs R
    (2018) The Neuroscience of Emotion: A New Synthesis (Princeton Univ Press, Princeton).
  17. ↵
    1. Sober E,
    2. Wilson DS
    (1998) Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior (Harvard Univ Press, Cambridge, MA).
  18. ↵
    1. Okasha S
    (2006) Evolution and the Levels of Selection (Oxford Univ Press, London).
  19. ↵
    1. Koonin EV
    (2011) The Logic of Chance: The Nature and Origin of Biological Evolution (FT Press, Upper Saddle River, NJ), 1st Ed.
  20. ↵
    1. Mameli M,
    2. Bateson P
    (2006) Innateness and the sciences. Biol Philos 21:155–188.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  21. ↵
    1. Price H
    (1996) Time’s Arrow and Archimede’s Point: Philosophical Reflections on Time and Physics (Oxford Univ Press, London).
  22. ↵
    1. Lewis D
    (1976) The paradoxes of time travel. Am Philos Q 13:145–152.
    OpenUrl
  23. ↵
    1. Rovelli C
    (2018) Physics needs philosophy. Philosophy needs physics. Found Phys 48:481–491.
    OpenUrl
  24. ↵
    1. Woese CR
    (2004) A new biology for a new century. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 68:173–186.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
PreviousNext
Back to top
Article Alerts
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on PNAS.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Opinion: Why science needs philosophy
(Your Name) has sent you a message from PNAS
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the PNAS web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Opinion: Why science needs philosophy
Lucie Laplane, Paolo Mantovani, Ralph Adolphs, Hasok Chang, Alberto Mantovani, Margaret McFall-Ngai, Carlo Rovelli, Elliott Sober, Thomas Pradeu
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Mar 2019, 116 (10) 3948-3952; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1900357116

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Request Permissions
Share
Opinion: Why science needs philosophy
Lucie Laplane, Paolo Mantovani, Ralph Adolphs, Hasok Chang, Alberto Mantovani, Margaret McFall-Ngai, Carlo Rovelli, Elliott Sober, Thomas Pradeu
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Mar 2019, 116 (10) 3948-3952; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1900357116
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Mendeley logo Mendeley
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences: 116 (10)
Table of Contents

Submit

Sign up for Article Alerts

Article Classifications

  • Biological Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Physical Sciences
  • Physics

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

You May Also be Interested in

Abstract depiction of a guitar and musical note
Science & Culture: At the nexus of music and medicine, some see disease treatments
Although the evidence is still limited, a growing body of research suggests music may have beneficial effects for diseases such as Parkinson’s.
Image credit: Shutterstock/agsandrew.
Scientist looking at an electronic tablet
Opinion: Standardizing gene product nomenclature—a call to action
Biomedical communities and journals need to standardize nomenclature of gene products to enhance accuracy in scientific and public communication.
Image credit: Shutterstock/greenbutterfly.
One red and one yellow modeled protein structures
Journal Club: Study reveals evolutionary origins of fold-switching protein
Shapeshifting designs could have wide-ranging pharmaceutical and biomedical applications in coming years.
Image credit: Acacia Dishman/Medical College of Wisconsin.
White and blue bird
Hazards of ozone pollution to birds
Amanda Rodewald, Ivan Rudik, and Catherine Kling talk about the hazards of ozone pollution to birds.
Listen
Past PodcastsSubscribe
Goats standing in a pin
Transplantation of sperm-producing stem cells
CRISPR-Cas9 gene editing can improve the effectiveness of spermatogonial stem cell transplantation in mice and livestock, a study finds.
Image credit: Jon M. Oatley.

Similar Articles

Site Logo
Powered by HighWire
  • Submit Manuscript
  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • RSS Feeds
  • Email Alerts

Articles

  • Current Issue
  • Latest Articles
  • Archive

PNAS Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Chemistry
  • Classics
  • Front Matter
  • Physics
  • Sustainability Science
  • Teaching Resources

Information

  • Authors
  • Editorial Board
  • Reviewers
  • Librarians
  • Press
  • Site Map
  • PNAS Updates

Feedback    Privacy/Legal

Copyright © 2021 National Academy of Sciences. Online ISSN 1091-6490