Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
    • Front Matter Portal
    • Journal Club
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses
  • Submit
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Accessibility Statement
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian

User menu

  • Log in
  • My Cart

Search

  • Advanced search
Home
Home
  • Log in
  • My Cart

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
    • Front Matter Portal
    • Journal Club
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses
  • Submit
Perspective

Rational policymaking during a pandemic

View ORCID ProfileLoïc Berger, View ORCID ProfileNicolas Berger, View ORCID ProfileValentina Bosetti, View ORCID ProfileItzhak Gilboa, View ORCID ProfileLars Peter Hansen, View ORCID ProfileChristopher Jarvis, View ORCID ProfileMassimo Marinacci, and View ORCID ProfileRichard D. Smith
  1. aCentre National de la Recherche Scientifique, IÉSEG School of Management, University of Lille, Unité Mixte de Recherche 9221–Lille Economics Management, 59000 Lille, France;
  2. bResources for the Future–Euro-Mediterranean Center on Climate Change (RFF-CMCC) European Institute on Economics and the Environment, Centro Euro-Mediterraneo sui Cambiamenti Climatici, 20123 Milan, Italy;
  3. cFaculty of Public Health and Policy, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine, London WC1H 9SH, United Kingdom;
  4. dDepartment of Epidemiology and Public Health, Sciensano (Belgian Scientific Institute of Public Health), 1050 Brussels, Belgium;
  5. eDepartment of Economics, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
  6. fInnocenzo Gasparini Institute for Economic Research, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
  7. gEconomics and Decision Sciences Department, École des Hautes Études Commerciales de Paris, 78351 Jouy-en-Josas, France;
  8. hEitan Berglas School of Economics, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel;
  9. iDepartment of Economics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
  10. jDepartment of Statistics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
  11. kBooth School of Business, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
  12. lDepartment of Infectious Disease Epidemiology, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine, London WC1E 7HT, United Kingdom;
  13. mDepartment of Decision Sciences, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
  14. nCollege of Medicine and Health, University of Exeter, Exeter EX1 2LU, United Kingdom

See allHide authors and affiliations

PNAS January 26, 2021 118 (4) e2012704118; https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2012704118
Loïc Berger
aCentre National de la Recherche Scientifique, IÉSEG School of Management, University of Lille, Unité Mixte de Recherche 9221–Lille Economics Management, 59000 Lille, France;
bResources for the Future–Euro-Mediterranean Center on Climate Change (RFF-CMCC) European Institute on Economics and the Environment, Centro Euro-Mediterraneo sui Cambiamenti Climatici, 20123 Milan, Italy;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Loïc Berger
  • For correspondence: l.berger@ieseg.fr lhansen@uchicago.edu
Nicolas Berger
cFaculty of Public Health and Policy, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine, London WC1H 9SH, United Kingdom;
dDepartment of Epidemiology and Public Health, Sciensano (Belgian Scientific Institute of Public Health), 1050 Brussels, Belgium;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Nicolas Berger
Valentina Bosetti
bResources for the Future–Euro-Mediterranean Center on Climate Change (RFF-CMCC) European Institute on Economics and the Environment, Centro Euro-Mediterraneo sui Cambiamenti Climatici, 20123 Milan, Italy;
eDepartment of Economics, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
fInnocenzo Gasparini Institute for Economic Research, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Valentina Bosetti
Itzhak Gilboa
gEconomics and Decision Sciences Department, École des Hautes Études Commerciales de Paris, 78351 Jouy-en-Josas, France;
hEitan Berglas School of Economics, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Itzhak Gilboa
Lars Peter Hansen
iDepartment of Economics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
jDepartment of Statistics, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
kBooth School of Business, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60637;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Lars Peter Hansen
  • For correspondence: l.berger@ieseg.fr lhansen@uchicago.edu
Christopher Jarvis
lDepartment of Infectious Disease Epidemiology, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine, London WC1E 7HT, United Kingdom;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Christopher Jarvis
Massimo Marinacci
fInnocenzo Gasparini Institute for Economic Research, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
mDepartment of Decision Sciences, Bocconi University, 20136 Milan, Italy;
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Massimo Marinacci
Richard D. Smith
cFaculty of Public Health and Policy, London School of Hygiene & Tropical Medicine, London WC1H 9SH, United Kingdom;
nCollege of Medicine and Health, University of Exeter, Exeter EX1 2LU, United Kingdom
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Richard D. Smith
  1. Edited by Ariel S. Pakes, Economics Department, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, and approved December 6, 2020 (received for review July 6, 2020)

  • Article
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Abstract

Policymaking during a pandemic can be extremely challenging. As COVID-19 is a new disease and its global impacts are unprecedented, decisions are taken in a highly uncertain, complex, and rapidly changing environment. In such a context, in which human lives and the economy are at stake, we argue that using ideas and constructs from modern decision theory, even informally, will make policymaking a more responsible and transparent process.

  • model uncertainty
  • ambiguity
  • robustness

The COVID-19 pandemic exposes decision problems faced by governments and international organizations. Policymakers are charged with taking actions to protect their population from the disease while lacking reliable information on the virus and its transmission mechanisms and on the effectiveness of possible measures and their (direct and indirect) health and socioeconomic consequences. The rational policy decision would combine the best available scientific evidence—typically provided by expert opinions and modeling studies. However, in an uncertain and rapidly changing environment, the pertinent evidence is highly fluid, making it challenging to produce scientifically grounded predictions of the outcomes of alternative courses of action.

A great deal of attention has been paid to how policymakers have handled uncertainty in the COVID-19 response (1⇓⇓⇓⇓–6). Policymakers have been confronted with very different views on the potential outbreak scenarios stemming from divergent experts’ assessments or differing modeling predictions. In the face of such uncertainty, policymakers may respond by attempting to balance the alternative perspectives, or they may fully embrace one without a concern that this can vastly misrepresent our underlying knowledge base (7). This tendency to lock on to a single narrative—or more generally, this inability to handle uncertainty—may result in overlooking valuable insights from alternative sources, and thus in misinterpreting the state of the COVID-19 outbreak, potentially leading to suboptimal decisions with possibly disastrous consequences (2, 8⇓–10).

This paper argues that insights from decision theory provide a valuable way to frame policy challenges and ambitions. Even if the decision-theory constructs are ultimately used only informally in practice, they offer a useful guide for transparent policymaking that copes with the severe uncertainty in sensible ways. First, we outline a framework to understand and guide decision-making under uncertainty in the COVID-19 pandemic context. Second, we show how formal decision rules could be used to guide policymaking and illustrate their use with the example of school closures. These decision rules allow policymakers to recognize that they do not know which of the many potential scenarios is “correct” and to act accordingly by taking precautionary and robust decisions, that is, that remain valid for a wide range of futures and keep options open (11). Third, we discuss directions to define a more transparent approach for communicating the degree of certainty in scientific findings and knowledge, particularly relevant to decision-makers managing pandemics.

Decision under Uncertainty

The Policymaker’s Problem(s).

The decision-making problem faced by a high-level government policymaker during a crisis like the COVID-19 pandemic is not trivial. In the first stage, when a new infectious disease appears, the policymaker may attempt to contain the outbreak by taking early actions to control onward transmission (e.g., isolation of confirmed and suspected cases and contact tracing). If this phase is unsuccessful, policymakers face a second-stage decision problem that consists of determining the appropriate level, timing, and duration of interventions to mitigate the course of clinical infection. These interventions may include banning mass gatherings, closing schools, and more extreme “lockdown” restrictions.

While these measures are expected to reduce the pandemic’s health burden by lowering the peak incidence, they also impose costs on society. For instance, they may have adverse impacts on mental health, domestic abuse, and job loss at a more personal level. Moreover, there are societal losses due to the immediate reduced economic activity coupled with a potentially prolonged recession and adverse impacts on longer-term health and social gradients. Policymakers must thus promptly cope with a complex and multifaceted picture of direct and indirect, proximal and distal, health, and socioeconomic trade-offs. In the acute phase of the pandemic, the trade-off between reducing mortality and morbidity and its associated socioeconomic consequences may seem relatively straightforward. Still, once out of this critical phase, most trade-offs are difficult and costly. How should the policymaker decide when and how to introduce or relax measures in a justifiable way, not just from a health and economic perspective but also politically? The answer critically depends on the prioritization and balance of potentially conflicting objectives (12).

Scientific Evidence and the Role of Modeling.

Scientific knowledge is foundational to the prevention, management, and treatment of global outbreaks. Some of this evidence can be summarized in pandemic preparedness and response plans (at both international and national levels) or might be directly obtained from panels of scientists with expertise in relevant areas of research, such as epidemiologists, infectious disease modelers, and social scientists. An essential part of the scientific evidence comes from quantitative models (13). Quantitative models are abstract representations of reality that provide a logically consistent way to organize thinking about the relationships among variables of interest. They combine what is known in general with what is known about the current outbreak to produce predictions to help guide policy decisions (14).

Epidemiological models (e.g., refs. 15 and 16) have been used to guide decision-making by assessing what is likely to happen to the transmission of the virus if policy interventions—either independently or in combination—were put in place. Such public health-oriented models are particularly useful in the short term to project the direct consequences of policy interventions on the epidemic trajectory and to guide decisions on resource allocations (17). As the measures put in place also largely affect the economic environment, decision-makers must, at least implicitly, confront trade-offs in the health- and nonhealth-related economic consequences. To weigh these trade-offs necessarily requires more than epidemiological models. For example, health policy analysis models, such as computable general equilibrium models, are used to simultaneously estimate the direct and indirect impacts of the outbreak on various aspects of the economy, such as labor supply, government budgets, or household consumption (18). More recent integrated assessment models combine economics and epidemiology by incorporating simplified epidemiological models of contagion within stylized dynamic economic frameworks. Such models address critical policy challenges by explicitly modeling dynamic adjustment paths and endogenous responses to changing incentives. They have been used to investigate the optimal policy response or alternative macroeconomic policies’ effectiveness to the economic shocks due to the COVID-19 pandemic (19⇓⇓–22). However, these different modeling approaches do not formally incorporate uncertainty; instead, they treat it ex-post, for example using sensitivity analyses.

Uncertainty.

Decisions within a pandemic context have to be made under overwhelming time pressure and amid high scientific uncertainty, with minimal quality evidence and potential disagreements among experts and models. In the COVID-19 outbreak, there was uncertainty about the virus’s essential characteristics, such as its transmissibility, severity, and natural history (3, 23, 24). This state of knowledge translates into uncertainty about the system dynamics, which renders uncertain the consequences of alternative policy interventions such as closing down schools or wearing masks in public. At a later stage of the pandemic, information overload becomes an issue, making it more difficult for the decision-maker to identify useful and good-quality evidence. The consequence is that, given the many uncertainties they are built on, no single model can be genuinely predictive in the context of an outbreak management strategy. Yet, if their results are used as insights providing potential quantitative stories among alternative ones, models can offer policymakers guidance by helping them understand the fragments of information available, uncover what might be going on, and eventually determine the appropriate policy response. The distinction between three layers of uncertainty—uncertainty within models, across models, and about models—can help the policymaker understand the extent of the problem (25⇓⇓–28).

Uncertainty within models reflects the standard notion of risk: uncertain outcomes with known probabilities. Models may include random shocks or impulses with prespecified distributions. It is the modeling counterpart to flipping coins or rolling dice in which we have full confidence in the probability assessment.

Uncertainty across models encompasses both the unknown parameters for a family of models or more discrete modeling differences in specification. Thus, it relates to unknown inputs needed to construct fully specified probability models. In the COVID-19 context, this corresponds, for example, to the uncertainty of some model parameters, such as how much transmission occurs in different age groups or how infectious people can be before they have symptoms. Existing data, if available and reliable, can help calibrate these model inputs. An additional challenge for the policymaker is the proliferation of modeling groups, researchers, and experts in various disciplines (epidemiology, economics, and other social sciences). Each of these provides forecasts and projections about the disease’s evolution and/or its socioeconomic consequences. This uncertainty across models and their consequent predictions may be difficult to handle by policymakers, especially as one approach is not necessarily superior to another but simply adds another perspective (29). There is no single “view.” Analysis of this form of uncertainty is typically the focal point of statistical approaches. Bayesian analyses, for instance, confront this via the use of subjective probabilities, whereas robust Bayesians explore sensitivity to prior inputs. Decision theory explores the ramifications of subjective uncertainty, as there might be substantial variation in the recommendations across different models and experts, reflecting other specific choices and assumptions regarding modeling type and structure.

Finally, as models are, by design, simplifications of more complex phenomena, they are necessarily misspecified, at least along some dimensions. For instance, they might not mention certain variables that matter, which modelers are or are not aware of, or they may be limited in the scope of functional relationships considered, unknown forms of specification and measurement errors, and so forth. Consequently, there is also uncertainty about the models’ assumptions and structures. It might sometimes be challenging, even for experts, to assess the merits and limits of alternative models and predictions.* This is what we mean in our reference to uncertainty about models.

How to Make Rational Decisions under Uncertainty?

Now that we have characterized the elements of the decision problem under uncertainty (Fig. 1), the question remains on how to make the best possible decision. In other words, how should the policymaker proceed to aggregate the different (and usually conflicting) scientific findings, model results, and expert opinions—which are all uncertain by construction and by lack of reliable data—and ultimately determine policy? Insights from modern decision theory are of the most significant value at this stage. They propose normative guidelines and “rules” to help policymakers make the best, that is, the most rational, decision under uncertainty.

Fig. 1.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 1.

Overview of the decision problem under uncertainty.

How Can Formal Decision Rules Be Useful?

The formal decision rules proposed by decision theorists are powerful, mathematically founded† tools that relate theoretical constructs and choice procedures to presumably observable data. Making a decision based on such rules is equivalent to complying implicitly with a set of general consistency conditions or principles governing human behavior. During a crisis such as the COVID-19 pandemic, using decision theory as a formal guide will lend credibility to policymaking by ensuring that the resulting actions are coherent and defensible. To illustrate how decision theory can serve as a coherence test (31), imagine the case of a policymaker trying to determine what the best response to the current pandemic is. The decision-makers can make up their minds by whatever mix of intuition, expert advice, imitation, and quantitative model results they have available and then check their judgment by asking whether they can justify the decision using a formal decision rule. Conceptually, it can be seen as a form of dialogue between the policymakers and decision theory, in which an attempt to justify a tentative decision helps to clarify the problem and, perhaps, leads to a different conclusion (32). Used this way, formal decision rules may help policymakers clarify the problem they are dealing with, test their intuition, eliminate strictly dominated options, and avoid reasoning mistakes and pitfalls that have been documented in psychological studies (e.g., confirmation bias, optimism bias, representativeness heuristic, prospect theory, etc.) (33).

Finally, because committees might investigate how decisions were taken during the crisis, for example about how lockdown measures were implemented and lifted, policymakers are held to account for the actions they took. A formal decision model can play an essential role in defending one’s choice and generating ex-post justifiability. For example, it could help a policymaker who had to decide which neighborhoods to keep under lockdown and which not to explain the process that led to such decisions to citizens who might think they have not been treated fairly.

Which Decision Rule to Follow?

As decision theory proposes a variety of different rules for decision-making under uncertainty, the call for using decision theory begs the question, Which rules to follow? The answer depends, in our opinion, on the society or organization in question. Decision theory should offer a gamut of models, and the people for whom decisions are made should find acceptable the model that is considered to “provide a justification” for a given decision. Thus, the answer ultimately depends on the policymakers’ characteristics, for example which conditions or behavioral principles they want to comply with, how prudent they want the policy to be, or what answer their constituency expects to receive. In Fig. 2, we present a simple example of school closures’ decision problem during the COVID-19 pandemic. We use this to demonstrate how distinct quantitative model outputs (some of which represent “best guesses” while others represent “reasonable worst-case”‡ possibilities) can be combined and used in formal decision rules, and what the resulting recommendations in terms of policy responses are.

Fig. 2.
  • Download figure
  • Open in new tab
  • Download powerpoint
Fig. 2.

Case study. School closures and their length during the COVID-19 pandemic (see refs. 52–69). Details are provided in SI Appendix.

The policymaker’s problem consists in finding the right balance between protecting the health and preventing economic and social disruptions by choosing whether and for how long to keep schools closed, given the scarce scientific evidence and the disagreement that may exist across model projections, possibly leading to significantly different policies.

The decision rules that we present differ primarily in how they handle probabilities. According to the Bayesian view, which holds that any source of uncertainty can be quantified probabilistically, the policymaker should always have well-defined probabilities about the impacts of the measures taken. If they rely on quantitative model outputs or expert advice to obtain different estimates, then they should attach a well-defined probability weight to each of these and compute an average. Thus, in the absence of objective probabilities, the decision-makers have their own subjective probabilities to guide decisions.

However, it may not always be rational to follow this approach (34⇓⇓–37). Its limitation stems from its inability to distinguish between uncertainty across models (which has an epistemic nature and is due to limited knowledge or ignorance) and uncertainty within models (which has an aleatory nature and is due to the intrinsic randomness in the world). In the response to the COVID-19 outbreak, the Bayesian approach requires the policymaker to express probabilistic beliefs (about the impact of a policy, about the correctness of a given model, etc.), without being told which probability it makes sense to adopt or being allowed to say “I don’t know.” Because of the disagreements that may exist across different model outputs, or expert opinions, another path may be to acknowledge one’s ignorance and relax the assumption that we can associate precise probabilities to any event. Modern decision theory proposes decision rules in line with this non-Bayesian approach. The axiomatic approach on which it is founded serves as an essential guide in understanding the merits and limitations of alternative ways to confront uncertainty formally. While we do not see this theory as settling on a single recipe for all decision problems, it adds important clarity to the rationale behind alternative decision rules.

Discussion

The decision rules presented in Fig. 2 are fully compatible with normative interpretations and could be particularly useful to design robust policies in this COVID-19 pandemic context. They assume that policymakers cope with uncertainty without reducing everything to risk, a pretension that tacitly presumes better information than they typically have. When exploring alternative courses of action, policymakers are necessarily unsure of the consequences. In such a context, sticking to the Bayesian expected utility paradigm not only requires substantive expertise (in weighting the pros and cons of alternative models) but also overshadows the policymaker’s reaction to the variability that may exist across models. While we focus, in Fig. 2, on a subset of decision rules, which can be checked for logical consistency, it should be clear, however, that other criteria, such as minmax regret (38), also exist and have been used in some applied contexts (39, 40). As mentioned above, we believe that a decision criterion is also a matter of personal preferences, which should somehow be aggregated over the different individuals for whom the decisions are made. Thus, the examples used in this paper are inevitably subjective, too.

We recognize the challenges in using decision theory when the decision-making process itself is complicated and many participants are involved with potentially different incentives. Nevertheless, we also see value to its use in less formal ways as guideposts to prudent decision-making and as a sensible way of framing the uncertainties in the trade-offs that policymakers are presented with.

In this example, the decision problem setup has been deliberately kept to minimal complexity to focus on the decision theory aspects. In particular, the set of actions is here limited to a single intervention (the duration of the school closure). In reality, the decision problem would, of course, require a much higher dimensional space (e.g., selective local closures, school dismissal, etc.), the interaction with other social distancing measures, or the ability to integrate start and stop times. Along the same lines, time constraints, learning, and dynamic considerations have been assumed away for the sake of tractability. In reality, it should be clear that the existence of deadlines could restrict which actions are feasible so that different sets of actions may correspond to different timings.

Similarly, as time passes, experts learn more about virus transmission and disease dynamics, which ultimately leads them to update their projections. Different “updating rules” allow incorporating such new information into the decision-making process. Our general message is the same as the one concerning the decision rules: The decision-maker should make her choice of the updating rule and be able to justify her decision based on this rule and the conditions that it does or does not satisfy. Finally, for expositional simplicity, we also abstracted from concerns about model misspecification, while recognizing this to be an integral part of how decision-makers should view the alternative models or perspectives that they confronted.

Concluding Remarks

During a period of crisis, policymakers, who make decisions on behalf of others, may be required to provide a protocol that suggests a decision-theoretic model supporting their decisions. Decision theory can contribute to a pandemic response by providing a way to organize a large amount of potentially conflicting scientific knowledge and providing rules for evaluating response options and turning them into concrete decision-making.

In this paper, we have highlighted the importance of quantitative modeling to support policy decisions [the same recommendation has also been made in other public health contexts (40)]. This use of models is common in different macroeconomic settings, including the assessments of monetary and fiscal policies. Some may see quantitative modeling as problematic because it requires seemingly arbitrary subjective judgments about the correctness of the different model specifications, leading them to prefer qualitative approaches. Even qualitative methods cannot escape the need for subjective inputs, however. Restricting scientific inputs to be only qualitative limits severely potentially valuable inputs into prudent policymaking. Instead, we argue in favor of using quantitative models and data, including explicit information about our underlying knowledge’s limits. We propose decision rules that incorporate the decisionmaker’s confidence in her subjective probabilities, thus rendering the decision-making process based on formal quantitative rules both robust and prudent.

In practical terms, ensuring that policy options are in line with formal decision rules could be achieved by having a decision analyst in the group of advisors to nurture a dialogue between policymakers and decision theory. This dialogue could clarify the trade-offs and encourage a more sanguine response to the uncertainties present when assessing the alternative courses of action and result in an improved policy outcome (31, 41).

To make the decision-making process under uncertainty more efficient, we also suggest acknowledging and communicating the various uncertainties transparently (42). For example, illustrating, quantifying, and discussing the multiple sources of uncertainty may help policymakers better understand their choices’ potential impact. To this aim, modelers should provide all information needed to reconstruct the analysis, including information about model structures, assumptions, and parameter values. Moreover, the way uncertainty around these choices affects model results needs to be accurately communicated, such as systematically reporting uncertainty boundaries around the estimates provided (43). Scientific and policy advisors would then need to synthesize all this information (32)—coming from diverse sources across different disciplines, possibly of different quality—to help policymakers turning it into actionable information for decisions, while making sure the complete range of uncertainty (including within and across models) is clearly reported and understood properly (44, 45).

One possible way to go is to enhance standardization by developing and adopting standard metrics to evaluate and communicate the degree of certainty in key findings. While several approaches have been proposed (46), insights could, for example, be gained from the virtues and the shortcomings of the reports of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (47). Another way is to develop further communication and collaboration between model developers and decision-makers to improve the quality and utility of models and the decisions they support (48).

Finally, while policymakers are responsible for making decisions, they are also responsible for communicating to professionals and the public. The way individuals respond to advice and measures selected is as vital as government actions, if not more (3). Communication should thus be an essential part of the policy response to uncertainty. In particular, government communication strategies to keep the public informed of what we [do not (49)] know should balance the costs and benefits of revealing information (how much, and in what form) (50).

As government strategies have been extensively debated in the media and models have become more scrutinized, one lesson learned from the COVID-19 management experience may be that policymakers and experts must increase their approaches’ transparency. Using the constructs from decision theory in policymaking, even in an informal way, will help ensure prudent navigation through the uncertainty that pervades this and possibly future pandemics. Being open about the degree of uncertainty surrounding the scientific evidence used to guide policy choices and allowing for the assumptions of the models used or for the decision-making process itself to be challenged is a valuable way of retaining public trust (51). At the same time, it is essential to counteract what is too often displayed by self-described experts who seek to influence policymakers and the public by projecting a pretense of knowledge that is likely to be false.

Materials

Supplementary information is included in SI Appendix, Methods Supplement to Figure 2.

Data Availability.

There are no data underlying this work.

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by Alfred P. Sloan Foundation Grant G-2018-11113; the AXA Chairs for Decision Sciences at HEC and in Risk at Bocconi University; the European Research Council under the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7-2007-2013; Grant 336703) and Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (Grant 670337); the French Agence Nationale de la Recherche under Grants ANR-17-CE03-0008-01, ANR-11-IDEX-0003, and ANR-11-LABX-0047; the Foerder Institute at Tel-Aviv University; and Israel Science Foundation Grant 1077/17.

Footnotes

  • ↵1L.B. and N.B. contributed equally to this work.

  • ↵2To whom correspondence may be addressed. Email: l.berger{at}ieseg.fr or lhansen{at}uchicago.edu.
  • Author contributions: L.B. and N.B. designed research; L.B., N.B., V.B., I.G., L.P.H., C.J., M.M., and R.D.S. performed research; L.B., N.B., V.B., I.G., L.P.H., C.J., M.M., and R.D.S. contributed new reagents/analytic tools; L.B., N.B., V.B., I.G., L.P.H., C.J., M.M., and R.D.S. analyzed data; and L.B., N.B., V.B., I.G., L.P.H., C.J., M.M., and R.D.S. wrote the paper.

  • The authors declare no competing interest.

  • This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.

  • ↵*Note that another way to see this additional layer of uncertainty is as uncertainty over predictions of alternative models that have not been developed yet.

  • ↵†Typically, each of these rules results from an axiomatization [i.e., an equivalence result taking the form of a theorem that relates a theoretical description of decision-making to conditions on observable data (30)].

  • ↵‡As these projections are typically premised on “reasonable” bounds in terms of their model inputs.

  • This article contains supporting information online at https://www.pnas.org/lookup/suppl/doi:10.1073/pnas.2012704118/-/DCSupplemental.

  • Copyright © 2021 the Author(s). Published by PNAS.

This open access article is distributed under Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives License 4.0 (CC BY-NC-ND).

References

  1. ↵
    1. M. Lazzerini,
    2. G. Putoto
    , COVID-19 in Italy: Momentous decisions and many uncertainties. Lancet Glob. Health 8, e641–e642 (2020).
    OpenUrl
  2. ↵
    1. N. Chater
    , Facing up to the uncertainties of COVID-19. Nat. Hum. Behav. 4, 439 (2020).
    OpenUrl
  3. ↵
    1. R. M. Anderson,
    2. H. Heesterbeek,
    3. D. Klinkenberg,
    4. T. D. Hollingsworth
    , How will country-based mitigation measures influence the course of the COVID-19 epidemic? Lancet 395, 931–934 (2020).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  4. ↵
    1. E. J. Emanuel et al
    ., Fair allocation of scarce medical resources in the time of covid-19. N. Engl. J. Med. 382, 2049–2055 (2020).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  5. ↵
    1. L. P. Hansen
    , “Using quantitative models to guide policy amid COVID-19 uncertainty” (White Paper, Becker Friedman Institute, Chicago, 2020).
  6. ↵
    1. C. F. Manski
    , Forming COVID-19 policy under uncertainty. J. Benefit Cost Anal. 1–16 (2020).
  7. ↵
    1. P. N. Johnson-Laird
    , Mental models and human reasoning. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107, 18243–18250 (2010).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  8. ↵
    1. A. Cancryn
    , “How overly optimistic modeling distorted Trump team’s coronavirus response.” Politico, 24 April 2020. https://www.politico.com/news/2020/04/24/trump-coronavirus-model-207582. Accessed 8 January 2021.
  9. ↵
    1. P. Rucker,
    2. J. Dawsey,
    3. Y. Abutaleb,
    4. R. Costa,
    5. L. H. Sun
    , 34 days of pandemic: Inside Trump’s desperate attempts to reopen America. Washington Post, 3 May 2020. https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/34-days-of-pandemic-inside-trumps-desperate-attempts-to-reopen-america/2020/05/02/e99911f4-8b54-11ea-9dfd-990f9dcc71fc_story.html. Accessed 8 January 2021.
  10. ↵
    1. The Editors
    , Dying in a leadership vacuum. N. Engl. J. Med. 383, 1479–1480 (2020).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  11. ↵
    1. R. J. Lempert,
    2. M. T. Collins
    , Managing the risk of uncertain threshold responses: Comparison of robust, optimum, and precautionary approaches. Risk Anal. 27, 1009–1026 (2007).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  12. ↵
    1. T. D. Hollingsworth,
    2. D. Klinkenberg,
    3. H. Heesterbeek,
    4. R. M. Anderson
    , Mitigation strategies for pandemic influenza A: Balancing conflicting policy objectives. PLoS Comput. Biol. 7, e1001076 (2011).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  13. ↵
    1. O. Morgan
    , How decision makers can use quantitative approaches to guide outbreak responses. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 374, 20180365 (2019).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  14. ↵
    1. S. den Boon et al
    ., Guidelines for multi-model comparisons of the impact of infectious disease interventions. BMC Med. 17, 163 (2019).
    OpenUrl
  15. ↵
    1. N. Ferguson et al
    ., “Impact of non-pharmaceutical interventions (NPIs) to reduce COVID19 mortality and healthcare demand” (Imperial College COVID-19 Response Team, 2020).
  16. ↵
    1. N. G. Davies,
    2. A. J. Kucharski,
    3. R. M. Eggo,
    4. A. Gimma,
    5. W. J. Edmunds; Centre for the Mathematical Modelling of Infectious Diseases COVID-19 working group
    , Effects of non-pharmaceutical interventions on COVID-19 cases, deaths, and demand for hospital services in the UK: A modelling study. Lancet Public Health 5, e375–e385 (2020).
    OpenUrlPubMed
  17. ↵
    1. I. Holmdahl,
    2. C. Buckee
    , Wrong but useful–What Covid-19 epidemiologic models can and cannot tell us. N. Engl. J. Med. 383, 303–305 (2020).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  18. ↵
    1. M. R. Keogh-Brown,
    2. H. T. Jensen,
    3. W. J. Edmunds,
    4. R. D. Smith
    , The impact of Covid-19, associated behaviours and policies on the UK economy: A computable general equilibrium model. SSM Popul. Health 100651 (2020).
  19. ↵
    1. M. S. Eichenbaum,
    2. S. Rebelo,
    3. M. Trabandt
    , The macroeconomics of epidemics. National Bureau of Economic Research [Preprint] (2020). http://doi.org/10.3386/w26882 (Accessed 9 April 2020).
  20. ↵
    1. V. Guerrieri,
    2. G. Lorenzoni,
    3. L. Straub,
    4. I. Werning
    , Macroeconomic implications of COVID-19: Can negative supply shocks cause demand shortages? National Bureau of Economic Research [Preprint] (2020). http://doi.org/10.3386/w26918 (Accessed 15 April 2020).
  21. ↵
    1. F. E. Alvarez,
    2. D. Argente,
    3. F. Lippi
    , A simple planning problem for COVID-19 lockdown, testing, and tracing. Am. Econ. Rev. Insights, in press.
  22. ↵
    1. L. Thunström,
    2. S. C. Newbold,
    3. D. Finnoff,
    4. M. Ashworth,
    5. J. F. Shogren
    , The benefits and costs of using social distancing to flatten the curve for COVID-19. J. Benefit Cost Anal. 11, 1–27 (2020).
    OpenUrl
  23. ↵
    1. J. Hellewell et al.; Centre for the Mathematical Modelling of Infectious Diseases COVID-19 Working Group
    , Feasibility of controlling COVID-19 outbreaks by isolation of cases and contacts. Lancet Glob. Health 8, e488–e496 (2020).
    OpenUrl
  24. ↵
    1. R. Li et al
    ., Substantial undocumented infection facilitates the rapid dissemination of novel coronavirus (SARS-CoV-2). Science 368, 489–493 (2020).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  25. ↵
    1. L. P. Hansen
    , Nobel lecture: Uncertainty outside and inside economic models. J. Polit. Econ. 122, 945–987 (2014).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  26. ↵
    1. M. Marinacci
    , Model uncertainty. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 13, 1022–1100 (2015).
    OpenUrl
  27. ↵
    1. L. P. Hansen,
    2. M. Marinacci
    , Ambiguity aversion and model misspecification: An economic perspective. Stat. Sci. 31, 511–515 (2016).
    OpenUrl
  28. ↵
    1. I. Aydogan,
    2. L. Berger,
    3. V. Bosetti,
    4. N. Liu
    , Three layers of uncertainty and the role of model misspecification. https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03031751/document. Accessed 30 November 2020.
  29. ↵
    1. S.-L. Li et al
    ., Essential information: Uncertainty and optimal control of Ebola outbreaks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 114, 5659–5664 (2017).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  30. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. A. Postlewaite,
    3. L. Samuelson,
    4. D. Schmeidler
    , What are axiomatizations good for? Theory Decis. 86, 339–359 (2019).
    OpenUrl
  31. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. L. Samuelson
    , What were you thinking?: Revealed preference theory as coherence test. https://econ.tau.ac.il/sites/economy.tau.ac.il/files/media_server/Economics/foerder/papers/Papers%202020/4-2020%20%20What%20Were%20You%20Thinking.pdf. Accessed 20 April 2020.
  32. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. M. Rouziou,
    3. O. Sibony
    , Decision theory made relevant: Between the software and the shrink. Res. Econ. 72, 240–250 (2018).
    OpenUrl
  33. ↵
    1. P. Cairney,
    2. R. Kwiatkowski
    , How to communicate effectively with policymakers: Combine insights from psychology and policy studies. Palgrave Commun. 3, 37 (2017).
    OpenUrl
  34. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. A. W. Postlewaite,
    3. D. Schmeidler
    , Probability and uncertainty in economic modeling. J. Econ. Perspect. 22, 173–188 (2008).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  35. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. A. Postlewaite,
    3. D. Schmeidler
    , Is it always rational to satisfy Savage’s axioms? Econ. Philos. 25, 285–296 (2009).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  36. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. A. Postlewaite,
    3. D. Schmeidler
    , Rationality of belief or: Why savage’s axioms are neither necessary nor sufficient for rationality. Synthese 187, 11–31 (2012).
    OpenUrl
  37. ↵
    1. D. Acemoglu,
    2. M. Arellano,
    3. E. Dekel
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. M. Marinacci
    , “Ambiguity and the Bayesian paradigm” in Advances in Economics and Econometrics: Tenth World Congress, Volume I: Economic Theory, D. Acemoglu, M. Arellano, E. Dekel, Eds. (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2013), pp. 179–242.
  38. ↵
    1. L. J. Savage
    , The theory of statistical decision. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 46, 55–67 (1951).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  39. ↵
    1. R. D. Smith
    , Is regret theory an alternative basis for estimating the value of healthcare interventions? Health Policy 37, 105–115 (1996).
    OpenUrlPubMed
  40. ↵
    1. C. F. Manski
    , Patient Care under Uncertainty (Princeton University Press, 2019).
  41. ↵
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. A. Postlewaite,
    3. L. Samuelson,
    4. D. Schmeidler
    , Economics: Between prediction and criticism. Int. Econ. Rev. 59, 367–390 (2018).
    OpenUrl
  42. ↵
    1. C. F. Manski
    , Communicating uncertainty in policy analysis. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 116, 7634–7641 (2019).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  43. ↵
    1. World Health Organization
    , WHO Guide for Standardization of Economic Evaluations of Immunization Programmes (World Health Organization, 2019).
  44. ↵
    1. D. Spiegelhalter,
    2. M. Pearson,
    3. I. Short
    , Visualizing uncertainty about the future. Science 333, 1393–1400 (2011).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  45. ↵
    1. V. Bosetti et al
    ., COP21 climate negotiators’ responses to climate model forecasts. Nat. Clim. Chang. 7, 185–190 (2017).
    OpenUrl
  46. ↵
    1. A. M. van der Bles et al
    ., Communicating uncertainty about facts, numbers and science. R. Soc. Open Sci. 6, 181870 (2019).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  47. ↵
    1. M. D. Mastrandrea et al
    ., “Guidance note for lead authors of the IPCC fifth assessment report on consistent treatment of uncertainties” (IPCC, 2010).
  48. ↵
    1. C. Rivers et al
    ., Using “outbreak science” to strengthen the use of models during epidemics. Nat. Commun. 10, 3102 (2019).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  49. ↵
    1. World Health Organization
    , Communicating Risk in Public Health Emergencies: A WHO Guideline for Emergency Risk Communication (ERC) Policy and Practice (World Health Organization, 2017).
  50. ↵
    1. D. Aikman et al
    ., Uncertainty in macroeconomic policy-making: Art or science? Philos. Trans. Royal Soc. Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 369, 4798–4817 (2011).
    OpenUrl
  51. ↵
    1. S. T. Fiske,
    2. C. Dupree
    , Gaining trust as well as respect in communicating to motivated audiences about science topics. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 111 (suppl. 4), 13593–13597 (2014).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    1. United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization
    , “COVID-19 educational disruption and response” (UNESCO, 2020).
    1. R. M. Viner et al
    ., School closure and management practices during coronavirus outbreaks including COVID-19: A rapid systematic review. Lancet Child Adolesc. Health 4, 397–404 (2020).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. J. Bayham,
    2. E. P. Fenichel
    , Impact of school closures for COVID-19 on the US health-care workforce and net mortality: A modelling study. Lancet Public Health 5, e271–e278 (2020).
    OpenUrl
    1. S. K. Brooks et al
    ., The impact of unplanned school closure on children’s social contact: Rapid evidence review. Euro Surveill. 25, 2000188 (2020).
    OpenUrl
    1. M. Z. Sadique,
    2. E. J. Adams,
    3. W. J. Edmunds
    , Estimating the costs of school closure for mitigating an influenza pandemic. BMC Public Health 8, 135 (2008).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. M. R. Keogh-Brown,
    2. R. D. Smith,
    3. J. W. Edmunds,
    4. P. Beutels
    , The macroeconomic impact of pandemic influenza: Estimates from models of the United Kingdom, France, Belgium and The Netherlands. Eur. J. Health Econ. 11, 543–554 (2010).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. H. Lempel,
    2. J. M. Epstein,
    3. R. A. Hammond
    , Economic cost and health care workforce effects of school closures in the U.S. PLoS Curr. 1, RRN1051 (2009).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. C. Jackson,
    2. P. Mangtani,
    3. E. Vynnycky
    , “Impact of school closures on an influenza pandemic: Scientific evidence base review” (Public Health England, London, 2014).
    1. G. W. Wong,
    2. A. M. Li,
    3. P. C. Ng,
    4. T. F. Fok
    , Severe acute respiratory syndrome in children. Pediatr. Pulmonol. 36, 261–266 (2003).
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. K. Prem et al.; Centre for the Mathematical Modelling of Infectious Diseases COVID-19 Working Group
    , The effect of control strategies to reduce social mixing on outcomes of the COVID-19 epidemic in Wuhan, China: A modelling study. Lancet Public Health 5, e261–e270 (2020).
    OpenUrlPubMed
    1. L. Berger,
    2. V. Bosetti
    , Are policymakers ambiguity averse? Econ. J. (Lond.) 130, 331–355 (2020).
    OpenUrl
    1. L. J. Savage
    , The Foundations of Statistics (Wiley, 1954), vol. J.
    1. S. Cerreia-Vioglio,
    2. F. Maccheroni,
    3. M. Marinacci,
    4. L. Montrucchio
    , Classical subjective expected utility. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 110, 6754–6759 (2013).
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    1. P. Klibanoff,
    2. M. Marinacci,
    3. S. Mukerji
    , A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73, 1849–1892 (2005).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
    1. A. Wald
    , Statistical Decision Functions (John Wiley & Sons, 1950).
    1. L. Hurwicz
    , Some specification problems and applications to econometric models. Econometrica 19, 343–344 (1951).
    OpenUrl
    1. I. Gilboa,
    2. D. Schmeidler
    , Maxmin expected utility with a non-unique prior. J. Math. Econ. 18, 141–154 (1989).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
    1. P. Ghirardato,
    2. F. Maccheroni,
    3. M. Marinacci
    , Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. J. Econ. Theory 118, 133–173 (2004).
    OpenUrlCrossRef
PreviousNext
Back to top
Article Alerts
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on PNAS.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Rational policymaking during a pandemic
(Your Name) has sent you a message from PNAS
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the PNAS web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Rational policymaking during a pandemic
Loïc Berger, Nicolas Berger, Valentina Bosetti, Itzhak Gilboa, Lars Peter Hansen, Christopher Jarvis, Massimo Marinacci, Richard D. Smith
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Jan 2021, 118 (4) e2012704118; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.2012704118

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Request Permissions
Share
Rational policymaking during a pandemic
Loïc Berger, Nicolas Berger, Valentina Bosetti, Itzhak Gilboa, Lars Peter Hansen, Christopher Jarvis, Massimo Marinacci, Richard D. Smith
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Jan 2021, 118 (4) e2012704118; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.2012704118
del.icio.us logo Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo CiteULike logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Mendeley logo Mendeley

Article Classifications

  • Biological Sciences
  • Immunology and Inflammation
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences: 118 (4)
Table of Contents

Submit

Sign up for Article Alerts

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • Decision under Uncertainty
    • How to Make Rational Decisions under Uncertainty?
    • Discussion
    • Concluding Remarks
    • Materials
    • Data Availability.
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Figures & SI
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

You May Also be Interested in

Setting sun over a sun-baked dirt landscape
Core Concept: Popular integrated assessment climate policy models have key caveats
Better explicating the strengths and shortcomings of these models will help refine projections and improve transparency in the years ahead.
Image credit: Witsawat.S.
Model of the Amazon forest
News Feature: A sea in the Amazon
Did the Caribbean sweep into the western Amazon millions of years ago, shaping the region’s rich biodiversity?
Image credit: Tacio Cordeiro Bicudo (University of São Paulo, São Paulo, Brazil), Victor Sacek (University of São Paulo, São Paulo, Brazil), and Lucy Reading-Ikkanda (artist).
Syrian archaeological site
Journal Club: In Mesopotamia, early cities may have faltered before climate-driven collapse
Settlements 4,200 years ago may have suffered from overpopulation before drought and lower temperatures ultimately made them unsustainable.
Image credit: Andrea Ricci.
Steamboat Geyser eruption.
Eruption of Steamboat Geyser
Mara Reed and Michael Manga explore why Yellowstone's Steamboat Geyser resumed erupting in 2018.
Listen
Past PodcastsSubscribe
Birds nestling on tree branches
Parent–offspring conflict in songbird fledging
Some songbird parents might improve their own fitness by manipulating their offspring into leaving the nest early, at the cost of fledgling survival, a study finds.
Image credit: Gil Eckrich (photographer).

Similar Articles

Site Logo
Powered by HighWire
  • Submit Manuscript
  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • RSS Feeds
  • Email Alerts

Articles

  • Current Issue
  • Special Feature Articles – Most Recent
  • List of Issues

PNAS Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Chemistry
  • Classics
  • Front Matter
  • Physics
  • Sustainability Science
  • Teaching Resources

Information

  • Authors
  • Editorial Board
  • Reviewers
  • Subscribers
  • Librarians
  • Press
  • Site Map
  • PNAS Updates
  • FAQs
  • Accessibility Statement
  • Rights & Permissions
  • About
  • Contact

Feedback    Privacy/Legal

Copyright © 2021 National Academy of Sciences. Online ISSN 1091-6490