Skip to main content
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Accessibility Statement
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian
  • Log in
  • My Cart

Main menu

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses
  • Submit
  • About
    • Editorial Board
    • PNAS Staff
    • FAQ
    • Accessibility Statement
    • Rights and Permissions
    • Site Map
  • Contact
  • Journal Club
  • Subscribe
    • Subscription Rates
    • Subscriptions FAQ
    • Open Access
    • Recommend PNAS to Your Librarian

User menu

  • Log in
  • My Cart

Search

  • Advanced search
Home
Home

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Articles
    • Current
    • Special Feature Articles - Most Recent
    • Special Features
    • Colloquia
    • Collected Articles
    • PNAS Classics
    • List of Issues
  • Front Matter
  • News
    • For the Press
    • This Week In PNAS
    • PNAS in the News
  • Podcasts
  • Authors
    • Information for Authors
    • Editorial and Journal Policies
    • Submission Procedures
    • Fees and Licenses

New Research In

Physical Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Physics
  • Chemistry
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Applied Mathematics
  • Applied Physical Sciences
  • Astronomy
  • Computer Sciences
  • Earth, Atmospheric, and Planetary Sciences
  • Engineering
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Mathematics
  • Statistics

Social Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Economic Sciences
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Political Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Social Sciences

Biological Sciences

Featured Portals

  • Sustainability Science

Articles by Topic

  • Agricultural Sciences
  • Anthropology
  • Applied Biological Sciences
  • Biochemistry
  • Biophysics and Computational Biology
  • Cell Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology
  • Environmental Sciences
  • Evolution
  • Genetics
  • Immunology and Inflammation
  • Medical Sciences
  • Microbiology
  • Neuroscience
  • Pharmacology
  • Physiology
  • Plant Biology
  • Population Biology
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Sustainability Science
  • Systems Biology
Research Article

Measurement invariance explains the universal law of generalization for psychological perception

View ORCID ProfileSteven A. Frank
PNAS first published September 10, 2018; https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1809787115
Steven A. Frank
aDepartment of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of California, Irvine, CA 92697-2525
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • ORCID record for Steven A. Frank
  • For correspondence: safrank@uci.edu
  1. Edited by Günter P. Wagner, Yale University, New Haven, CT, and approved August 15, 2018 (received for review June 7, 2018)

  • Article
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

Significance

When an animal is presented with two stimuli, it may consider them similar or different. Similarity often expresses a generalized notion of a category, such as two circles with different sizes, shadings, and colors both being circles. In many studies, perception of similarity declines exponentially with the measure of separation, a pattern often called the universal law of generalization. This article shows that the universal exponential law can be explained by simple properties any reasonable perceptual scale must have. A shift of the scale by a constant amount, or a stretch by a constant amount, should not change the animal’s ability to perceive generalities or differences. Those invariant measurement properties by themselves explain why perceived generalization follows an exponential pattern.

Abstract

The universal law of generalization describes how animals discriminate between alternative sensory stimuli. On an appropriate perceptual scale, the probability that an organism perceives two stimuli as similar typically declines exponentially with the difference on the perceptual scale. Exceptions often follow a Gaussian probability pattern rather than an exponential pattern. Previous explanations have been based on underlying theoretical frameworks such as information theory, Kolmogorov complexity, or empirical multidimensional scaling. This article shows that the few inevitable invariances that must apply to any reasonable perceptual scale provide a sufficient explanation for the universal exponential law of generalization. In particular, reasonable measurement scales of perception must be invariant to shift by a constant value, which by itself leads to the exponential form. Similarly, reasonable measurement scales of perception must be invariant to multiplication, or stretch, by a constant value, which leads to the conservation of the slope of discrimination with perceptual difference. In some cases, an additional assumption about exchangeability or rotation of underlying perceptual dimensions leads to a Gaussian pattern of discrimination, which can be understood as a special case of the more general exponential form. The three measurement invariances of shift, stretch, and rotation provide a sufficient explanation for the universally observed patterns of perceptual generalization. All of the additional assumptions and language associated with information, complexity, and empirical scaling are superfluous with regard to the broad patterns of perception.

  • scaling patterns
  • categorization
  • sensory information
  • animal behavior
  • probability theory

The probability that an organism perceives two stimuli as similar typically decays exponentially with separation between the stimuli. The exponential decay in perceptual similarity is often referred to as the universal law of generalization (1, 2).

“Generalization” arises because perceived similarity may describe recognition of a general category. For example, two circles may have different sizes, colors, and shadings. Perceived similarity arises from the generalized perception of “circle” as a category.

“Universal law” arises because many empirical observations fit the pattern for diverse sensory modalities across different species. Typical exceptions take on a Gaussian probability pattern for perceived separation (3).

Both theory and empirical analysis depend on the definition of the perceptual scale. How does one translate the perceived differences between two circles with different properties into a quantitative measurement scale?

There are many different suggestions in the literature for how to define a perceptual scale. Each of those suggestions develop very specific notions of measurement based, for example, on information theory, Kolmogorov complexity theory, or multidimensional scaling descriptions derived from observations (1, 2, 4).

I focus on the minimal properties that any reasonable perceptual measurement scale must have rather than on detailed assumptions motivated by external theories of information, complexity, or empirical scaling. I express the minimal properties as simple invariances.

I show that a few inevitable invariances of any reasonable perceptual scale determine the exponential form for the universal law of generalization in perception. All of the other details of information, complexity, and empirical scaling are superfluous with respect to understanding why the universal law of generalization has the exponential form.

I also show that, when the separation between stimuli depends on various underlying perceptional dimensions, it sometimes makes sense to assume that the perceptual scale will also obey exchangeability or rotational invariance. When that additional invariance holds, the universal law takes on the Gaussian form, which I show to be a special case of the general exponential form.

Basic Problem and Notation

Chater and Vitányi (ref. 2, p. 346) state the law as “the probability of perceiving similarity or analogy between two items, a and b, is a negative exponential function of the distance d(a,b) between them in an internal psychological space.”

Let the notation P(Rb|Sa) describe the probability of a positive response, Rb, to the event b, given an initial stimulus, Sa, by the event a. A positive response expresses the perceived similarity of b to a, which may also be thought of as expressing the generalization that b and a belong to the same category.

The goal here is to understand how the perceived similarity of b to a, observed as Rb|Sa, translates into a continuous psychological measurement scale, Tb|a, so thatP(Rb|Sa)≡f(Tb|a)[1]for a suitably defined mapping Rb|Sa↦Tb|a and probability distribution function, f. We seek the characteristics of the mapping and the associated function, f.

Invariant Properties of Measurement

There are many different suggestions in the literature for how to define a perceptual scale, Tb|a (1, 2, 4). I focus on the minimal properties that any reasonable measurement scale must have, rather than on detailed assumptions motivated by external theories (5⇓–7). I express the minimal properties as simple invariances. Before listing the invariances, consider two simple examples.

First, suppose we wish to analyze the perception of temperature for event b, given that event a is at the freezing point for water. If we choose to measure the temperature on the Celsius scale, then Ta|a=0 and Tb|a=C. It would make sense to assume that perceptual generalization would be identical if we assigned numerical values on a Fahrenheit scale, T̃, which we obtain by T̃b|a=32+1.8Tb|a.

Second, suppose we wish to measure the perception of separation between two potentially dangerous prey items, such as noxious butterflies (4, 8). We begin by exposing a noxious butterfly, a, to a predator. After the predator tastes butterfly a, we then expose butterfly b to the same predator. For the exposure to b, we measure the tendency for the predator to attack the potential prey item. Data may include the directions of movements relative to the butterfly, attacks per minute, or the probability of attack over repeated experiments. We now wish to find a scale, Tb|a, that is a function of the data we have for the response to various butterflies, b, relative to an initial stimulus butterfly, a.

However we choose that scale, it makes sense to suppose that the information in Tb|a about the perceptual separation between b and a is the same as the information in α+βTb|a for some constants α and β. If that were not so, it would be equivalent to saying that the analogs of Celsius and Fahrenheit scalings would provide different information about the perceptual separation between the two butterflies.

For example, we may wish to set Ta|a=0 to describe a zero separation between identical butterflies, or we may wish to let Ta|a express the amount of the baseline predator perception of the separation between identical stimuli. In either case, our scale T should contain the same information with respect to the probabilities of response given in Eq. 1. Here, similarity associates with the probability of avoidance response. We may also wish to express our scale standardized with respect to a unit response, Tb*|a, to b*, or with respect to a unit response, Tb†|a, to b†. The constant multiplications required to transform between units of measure should not alter the information in the perceptual scale, T, about the probabilities of response.

Affine and Rotational Invariance

In other words, the way in which we measure perceptual distance between two stimuli should be independent of a shift and stretch of the scale by constant values. Formally, the scale should be shift invariant with respect to any constant, α, such thatf(Tb|a)=kαf(Tb|a+α)[2]for some constant of proportionality, kα. The scale should also be stretch invariant to any constant, β, such thatf(λTb|a)=f(λββTb|a),[3]for which I show below that λ=λββ is an invariant constant that is conserved in any particular application, set by the fact that 1/λ is the average value on the perceptual scale for positive responses to varying events b for a given stimulus a.

Thus, the scale Tb|a has the property that the associated probability pattern is invariant to the affine transformation of shift and stretch, Tb|a↦α+βTb|a. I will show that affine invariance by itself determines the exponential form for the universal law of generalization in perception.

In some cases, it makes sense to assume that the perceptual scale should also obey rotational invariance, such that the Pythagorean partitionTb|a=y12(θ)+y22(θ)[4]splits the measurement into components that add invariantly to Tb|a for any value of the parameter θ. The invariant quantity Tb|a defines a circle in the (y1,y2) plane with a conserved radius Rb|a=Tb|a that is invariant to θ, the angle of rotation around the circle, circumscribing a conserved area πRb|a2=πTb|a.

Rotational invariance partitions a conserved quantity into additive components, for which the order may be exchanged without altering the invariant quantity. When rotational invariance holds, the universal law takes on a Gaussian form, which we will see to be a special case of the general exponential form.

The following sections develop the three invariances of shift, stretch, and rotation. I show that essentially all of the common properties of perceptual generalization follow from these invariances. The analysis here briefly summarizes the detailed development described in Frank (9). The novelty in this article concerns the simple understanding of widely observed psychological patterns.

Shift Invariance Implies the Exponential Form

To simplify notation, denote the perceptual scale by x≡Tb|a and the associated probability distribution by f(x)≡f(Tb|a). If we assume that the functional form for the probability distribution, f, is invariant to a constant shift of the perceptual scale, x+α, then by the conservation of total probability∫k0f(x) dx=∫kαf(x+α) dx=1[5]holds for any magnitude of the shift, α, in which the proportionality constant, kα, changes with the magnitude of the shift, α, independently of the value of x, to satisfy the conservation of total probability.

From this equality for total probability, which holds for any shift α by adjustment of the constant, kα, the condition for x≡Tb|a to be a shift-invariant scale is equivalent tof(x+α)=καf(x),[6]in which κα depends only on α and is independent of x. Because the invariance holds for any shift, α, it must hold for an infinitesimal shift, α=ϵ. We can write the Taylor series expansion for an infinitesimal shift asf(x+ϵ)=f(x)+ϵf′(x)=κϵf(x),with κϵ=1−λϵ, because ϵ is small and independent of x, and κ0=1. Thus,f′(x)=−λf(x)is a differential equation with solutionf(x)=ke−λx,[7]in which k is determined by the conservation of total probability. When the perceptual scale ranges over positive values, x>0, then k=λ.

The assumption that a perceptual scale must be shift invariant is, by itself, sufficient to explain the exponential form of the universal law of generalization.

The Exponential Form Implies Shift Invariance

The previous section showed that if the perceptual scale, x, is shift invariant, then the exponential form of the universal law of generalization follows. This section shows that if the universal law of generalization takes on the exponential form, then the underlying perceptual scale must be shift invariant. Thus, shift invariance is necessary and sufficient for the exponential form. Any assumptions about the perceptual scale beyond shift invariance must be superfluous with respect to the exponential form.

Begin with the assumption of the exponential form in Eq. 7 and write the consequence of a shift of the scale x by α asf(x+α)=kαe−λ(x+α)=kαe−λαe−λx=ke−λxin which kα=keλα because the constant multiplier of the exponential must be chosen to satisfy the conservation of total probability, in other words, to normalize the total probability to be one. Thus, the exponential form implies shift invariance of the perceptual scale, x.

Stretch Invariance and Rate of Perceptual Change

If we assume that the perceptual scale is defined for positive values, x>0, then the average value of λx is always one, because∫0∞λxf(x)dx=λ∫0∞λxe−λxdx=1.Thus, for average value, x¯, the value of λ is 1/x¯. We can think of x¯ as the average discrimination of various events, b, relative to an initial stimulus, a, in which the set of events b corresponds to a uniform continuum along the perceptual scale, x.

It makes sense to assume that the average discrimination would not change if we arbitrarily multiplied our numerical scale for perception, x, by a constant, β. The conservation of average value and stretch invariance are equivalent, becauseλ∫0∞λββxe−λββxdx=1when we allow λβ to adjust to satisfy the conservation of average value so that λ=λββ or, equivalently, we assume stretch invariance of the scale, x≡Tb|a.

The constant λ=1/x¯ can be thought of as the slope or rate of change in the logarithm of discrimination, becauselog⁡f(x)=−λx.Stretch invariance, or the conservation of average value, is sufficient to set the rate of change in the logarithm of discrimination. The average value of −logf(x) is a common definition of information or entropy and is related to many interpretations in terms of information theory (4, 10).

Rotational Invariance and Gaussian Patterns

The scale, x, measures the perceptual difference between two entities or events. In some cases, the total difference, x, depends on the perceived differences along several distinct underlying dimensions. With two underlying dimensions, we may writex=z1(θ)+z2(θ).For a particular value of x, the parameter θ describes all of the combinations of the two underlying dimensions that add invariantly to x. If we let x=r2 and let the dependence of z on θ be implicit, we can write the prior expression equivalently asx=r2=z12+z22,which defines a circle with coordinates along the positive and negative values of (z1,z2), with a constant radius r that is rotationally invariant with respect to the parametric angle, θ. Traditionally, one uses yi=zi, so that the radius, r, of a sphere has the familiar definition of a Euclidean distancer2=∑yi2.For each radial value, r=x, we can write {yi(θ)} as the sets indexed by the parameter θ for which the individual dimensional measures combine to the same invariant radius. If the angles of rotation with equivalent radius occur with equal probability or without prior bias, then radial values are rotationally invariant with respect to probability or prior likelihood.

I now show that rotational invariance leads to the Gaussian pattern as a special case of the general exponential form. In the exponential form derived in earlier sections, λx described the stretch-invariant perceptual scale. To express that scale in terms of a rotationally invariant radial measure, r, we note that x=r2 and we let λ=πv2. Thus, we can write the stretch-invariant incremental perceptual measure asλdx=πv2dr2=2πv2rdr.The general exponential form isf(x)dx=λe−λxdx=2πv2re−πv2r2dr.At a given radius, vr, if, by rotational invariance, all combinations of values for the underlying measurement dimensions occur without bias or prior information, then the total probability in a radial increment, vdr, is spread uniformly over the circumferential path with length 2πvr.

A radial vector intersects a fraction of the total probability density in the circumferential path in proportion to 1/2πvr. Thus, the probability along an increment vdr of the radial vector is(1/2πvr)f(x)dx=ve−πv2r2dr=ve−λr2dr,invariantly with respect to the angle of orientation of the radial vector. This expression is the Gaussian distribution, with r2 as the squared deviation from the mean or central location and with parameters commonly written as λ=1/2σ2 and v=1/2πσ2 for variance σ2. The variance is simply the average value of the squared radial deviations, r2=x.

We can also write the Gaussian in terms of the standard perceptual scale, x, asg(x)dx=ve−λxdx.When we consider the standard perceptual scale, x, with respect to the incremental square-root scale, dx, we obtain a Gaussian. The incremental square-root scale makes sense when we consider x as an aggregate measure of the sum of underlying perceptual dimensions. Each dimension naturally takes on a square-root scaling relative to the invariant total distance, because of the Euclidean measure of squared distance as the sum of squares along each dimension.

Discussion

Any reasonable perceptual scale must satisfy the simple affine invariances of shift and stretch. I have shown that those invariances are sufficient to explain the exponential form of the universal law of generalization. I have also shown that an additional common invariance of rotation explains why some observed patterns of generalization follow a Gaussian rather than an exponential pattern. The Gaussian pattern is, in fact, a special case of exponential scaling, when the scale is a squared Euclidean distance over several underlying dimensions.

Previous explanations also generate the exponential pattern of the universal law (1, 2, 4). The reason those explanations succeed is that they include assumptions about shift invariance, which by itself generates an exponential pattern. All of the other assumptions and language associated with those prior explanations are superfluous with respect to the exponential form. Conclusions about rate of change in discrimination typically associate with an assumption about stretch invariance or, equivalently, conservation of average value.

It is certainly true that additional assumptions will lead to more precise predictions, which may then be tested to rule out particular mechanisms. But those additional assumptions and tests do not directly bear on the general exponential form itself.

I do not know of explicit prior explanations that unify the Gaussian pattern with the universal exponential law. Such explanations, if they exist, will generally reduce to the assumption of rotational invariance. Again, additional assumptions or arguments about particular underlying mechanisms are superfluous with regard to the general pattern.

It is, of course, interesting to consider what underlying perceptual mechanisms lead to the universal law. However, almost certainly, there is no single mechanism that could explain such a widely observed pattern. General patterns require general explanations that apply broadly. The simple invariances of meaningful measurement scales provide that general explanation for the observed patterns of perceptual scaling.

Acknowledgments

National Science Foundation Grant DEB–1251035 and the Donald Bren Foundation support my research. I completed this work while on sabbatical in the Theoretical Biology group of the Institute for Integrative Biology at Eidgenössische Technische Hochschule (ETH) Zürich.

Footnotes

  • ↵1Email: safrank{at}uci.edu.
  • Author contributions: S.A.F. designed research, performed research, and wrote the paper.

  • The author declares no conflict of interest.

  • This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.

Published under the PNAS license.

View Abstract

References

  1. ↵
    1. Shepard RN
    (1987) Toward a universal law of generalization for psychological science. Science 237:1317–1323.
    .
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  2. ↵
    1. Chater N,
    2. Vitányi PMB
    (2003) The generalized universal law of generalization. J Math Psychol 47:346–369.
    .
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  3. ↵
    1. Ghirlanda S,
    2. Enquist M
    (2003) A century of generalization. Anim Behav 66:15–36.
    .
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  4. ↵
    1. Sims CR
    (2018) Efficient coding explains the universal law of generalization in human perception. Science 360:652–656.
    .
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  5. ↵
    1. Luce RD,
    2. Narens L
    (2008) Measurement, theory of. The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, eds Durlauf SN, Blume LE (Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK).
    .
  6. ↵
    1. Narens L,
    2. Luce RD
    (2008) Meaningfulness and invariance. The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, eds Durlauf SN, Blume LE (Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK).
    .
  7. ↵
    1. Houle D,
    2. Pelabon C,
    3. Wagner GP,
    4. Hansen TF
    (2011) Measurement and meaning in biology. Q Rev Biol 86:3–34.
    .
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  8. ↵
    1. Brower JVZ
    (1958) Experimental studies of mimicry in some North American butterflies: Part I. The monarch, Danaus plexippus, and viceroy, Limenitis archippus archippus. Evolution 12:32–47.
    .
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  9. ↵
    1. Frank SA
    (2016) Common probability patterns arise from simple invariances. Entropy 18:192.
    .
    OpenUrl
  10. ↵
    1. Cover TM,
    2. Thomas JA
    (1991) Elements of Information Theory (Wiley, New York).
    .
PreviousNext
Back to top
Article Alerts
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on PNAS.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
Measurement invariance explains the universal law of generalization for psychological perception
(Your Name) has sent you a message from PNAS
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the PNAS web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
Measurement invariance explains the universal law of generalization for psychological perception
Steven A. Frank
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Sep 2018, 201809787; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1809787115

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
Request Permissions
Share
Measurement invariance explains the universal law of generalization for psychological perception
Steven A. Frank
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Sep 2018, 201809787; DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1809787115
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like
  • Mendeley logo Mendeley
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences: 118 (4)
Current Issue

Submit

Sign up for Article Alerts

Article Classifications

  • Biological Sciences
  • Psychological and Cognitive Sciences
  • Physical Sciences
  • Applied Mathematics

Jump to section

  • Article
    • Abstract
    • Basic Problem and Notation
    • Invariant Properties of Measurement
    • Affine and Rotational Invariance
    • Shift Invariance Implies the Exponential Form
    • The Exponential Form Implies Shift Invariance
    • Stretch Invariance and Rate of Perceptual Change
    • Rotational Invariance and Gaussian Patterns
    • Discussion
    • Acknowledgments
    • Footnotes
    • References
  • Info & Metrics
  • PDF

You May Also be Interested in

Abstract depiction of a guitar and musical note
Science & Culture: At the nexus of music and medicine, some see disease treatments
Although the evidence is still limited, a growing body of research suggests music may have beneficial effects for diseases such as Parkinson’s.
Image credit: Shutterstock/agsandrew.
Large piece of gold
News Feature: Tracing gold's cosmic origins
Astronomers thought they’d finally figured out where gold and other heavy elements in the universe came from. In light of recent results, they’re not so sure.
Image credit: Science Source/Tom McHugh.
Dancers in red dresses
Journal Club: Friends appear to share patterns of brain activity
Researchers are still trying to understand what causes this strong correlation between neural and social networks.
Image credit: Shutterstock/Yeongsik Im.
Yellow emoticons
Learning the language of facial expressions
Aleix Martinez explains why facial expressions often are not accurate indicators of emotion.
Listen
Past PodcastsSubscribe
Goats standing in a pin
Transplantation of sperm-producing stem cells
CRISPR-Cas9 gene editing can improve the effectiveness of spermatogonial stem cell transplantation in mice and livestock, a study finds.
Image credit: Jon M. Oatley.

Similar Articles

Site Logo
Powered by HighWire
  • Submit Manuscript
  • Twitter
  • Facebook
  • RSS Feeds
  • Email Alerts

Articles

  • Current Issue
  • Special Feature Articles – Most Recent
  • List of Issues

PNAS Portals

  • Anthropology
  • Chemistry
  • Classics
  • Front Matter
  • Physics
  • Sustainability Science
  • Teaching Resources

Information

  • Authors
  • Editorial Board
  • Reviewers
  • Librarians
  • Press
  • Site Map
  • PNAS Updates

Feedback    Privacy/Legal

Copyright © 2021 National Academy of Sciences. Online ISSN 1091-6490