Free access

The logic of indirect speech

Edited by Jeremy Nathans, Johns Hopkins University School of Medicine, Baltimore, MD, and approved December 11, 2007
January 22, 2008
105 (3) 833-838

Abstract

When people speak, they often insinuate their intent indirectly rather than stating it as a bald proposition. Examples include sexual come-ons, veiled threats, polite requests, and concealed bribes. We propose a three-part theory of indirect speech, based on the idea that human communication involves a mixture of cooperation and conflict. First, indirect requests allow for plausible deniability, in which a cooperative listener can accept the request, but an uncooperative one cannot react adversarially to it. This intuition is supported by a game-theoretic model that predicts the costs and benefits to a speaker of direct and indirect requests. Second, language has two functions: to convey information and to negotiate the type of relationship holding between speaker and hearer (in particular, dominance, communality, or reciprocity). The emotional costs of a mismatch in the assumed relationship type can create a need for plausible deniability and, thereby, select for indirectness even when there are no tangible costs. Third, people perceive language as a digital medium, which allows a sentence to generate common knowledge, to propagate a message with high fidelity, and to serve as a reference point in coordination games. This feature makes an indirect request qualitatively different from a direct one even when the speaker and listener can infer each other's intentions with high confidence.

Continue Reading

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS.

We thank Peter Gärdenfors and two anonymous reviewers for comments on an earlier draft. This work was supported by National Institutes of Health Grant R01 HD-18381 (to S.P.).

References

1
P Brown, SC Levinson Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage (Cambridge Univ Press, New York, 1987).
2
HH Clark Using Language (Cambridge Univ Press, New York, 1996).
3
TM Holtgraves Language as Social Action (Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ, 2002).
4
S Pinker The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature (Viking, New York, 2007).
5
HP Grice, Logic and conversation. Syntax & Semantics, eds P Cole, JL Morgan (Academic, New York) Vol 3 (1975).
6
GC Williams Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought (Princeton Univ Press, Princeton, 1966).
7
R Trivers Social Evolution (Benjamin/Cummings, Reading, MA, 1985).
8
R Dawkins, JR Krebs, Animal signals: Information or manipulation? Behavioral Ecology, eds JR Krebs, NB Davies (Blackwell, Oxford), pp. 282–309 (1978).
9
TC Schelling The Strategy of Conflict (Harvard Univ Press, Cambridge, MA, 1960).
10
B Feiler Pocketful of dough. Gourmet, pp. 99–101 (2000).
11
AP Fiske, The four elementary forms of sociality: Framework for a unified theory of social relations. Psychol Rev 99, 689–723 (1992).
12
J Maynard Smith Evolution and the Theory of Games (Cambridge Univ Press, New York, 1982).
13
AP Fiske, Four modes of constituting relationships: Consubstantial assimilation; space, magnitude, time, and force; concrete procedures; abstract symbolism. Relational Models Theory: A Contemporary Overview, ed N Haslam (Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ, 2004).
14
WD Hamilton, The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. J Theor Biol 7, 1–16 (1964).
15
WD Hamilton, The genetical evolution of social behaviour. II. J Theor Biol 7, 17–52 (1964).
16
RD Alexander The Biology of Moral Systems (Aldine de Gruyter, Hawthorne, NY, 1987).
17
J Tooby, L Cosmides, Friendship and the Banker's Paradox: Other pathways to the evolution of adaptations for altruism. Proc Brit Acad 88, 119–143 (1996).
18
R Trivers, The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q Rev Biol 46, 35–57 (1971).
19
MA Nowak, Five rules for the evolution of cooperation. Science 314, 1560–1563 (2006).
20
S Pinker The Language Instinct (HarperCollins, New York, 1994).
21
M Reddy, The conduit metaphor: A case of frame conflict in our language about language. Metaphor and Thought, ed A Ortony (Cambridge Univ Press, New York, 1993).
22
D Kahneman, A Tversky, Prospect theory: An analysis of decisions under risk. Econometrica 47, 313–327 (1979).
23
E Goffman The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life (Doubleday, New York, 1959).
24
MA Nowak, K Sigmund, Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image scoring. Nature 393, 573–577 (1998).
25
P Vanderschraaf, G Sillari, Entry for “common knowledge.”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed EN Zalta (Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University, Stanford, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2005/entries/common-knowledge/. (2005).
26
SR Schiffer Meaning (Oxford Univ Press, New York, 1972).
27
DK Lewis Convention: A Philosophical Study (Harvard Univ Press, Cambridge, MA, 1969).
28
, ed NV Smith (Academic, New York Mutual Knowledge, 1982).
29
HH Clark, CR Marshall, Definite reference and mutual knowledge. Elements of Discourse Understanding, eds AK Joshi, BL Webber, IA Sag (Cambridge Univ Press, New York), pp. 10–63 (1991).
30
MS-Y Chwe Rational Ritual: Culture, Coordination, and Common Knowledge (Princeton Univ Press, Princeton, 2001).

Information & Authors

Information

Published in

The cover image for PNAS Vol.105; No.3
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
Vol. 105 | No. 3
January 22, 2008
PubMed: 18199841

Submission history

Received: July 31, 2007
Published online: January 22, 2008
Published in issue: January 22, 2008

Acknowledgments

We thank Peter Gärdenfors and two anonymous reviewers for comments on an earlier draft. This work was supported by National Institutes of Health Grant R01 HD-18381 (to S.P.).

Notes

This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.

Authors

Affiliations

Steven Pinker [email protected]
Department of Psychology, and
Martin A. Nowak
Program for Evolutionary Dynamics, Departments of Mathematics and Organismic and Evolutionary Biology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138
James J. Lee
Department of Psychology, and

Notes

To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail: [email protected]
Author contributions: S.P. and M.A.N. designed research; J.J.L. performed research; J.J.L. analyzed data; and S.P. wrote the paper.

Competing Interests

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Metrics & Citations

Metrics

Note: The article usage is presented with a three- to four-day delay and will update daily once available. Due to ths delay, usage data will not appear immediately following publication. Citation information is sourced from Crossref Cited-by service.


Citation statements

Altmetrics

Citations

Export the article citation data by selecting a format from the list below and clicking Export.

Cited by

    Loading...

    View Options

    View options

    PDF format

    Download this article as a PDF file

    DOWNLOAD PDF

    Login options

    Check if you have access through your login credentials or your institution to get full access on this article.

    Personal login Institutional Login

    Recommend to a librarian

    Recommend PNAS to a Librarian

    Purchase options

    Purchase this article to access the full text.

    Single Article Purchase

    The logic of indirect speech
    Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
    • Vol. 105
    • No. 3
    • pp. 827-1098

    Media

    Figures

    Tables

    Other

    Share

    Share

    Share article link

    Share on social media